Orthogenesis

Evolutionary progress as a tree of life. Ernst Haeckel, 1866

Orthogenesis also known as orthogenetic evolution, progressive evolution, evolutionary progress, or progressionism, is the controversial biological hypothesis that organisms have an innate tendency to evolve in a definite direction towards some goal (teleology) due to some internal mechanism or "driving force".[1][2][3] According to the theory, the largest-scale trends in evolution have an absolute goal such as increasing biological complexity. Prominent historical figures who have championed some form of evolutionary progress include Jean-Baptiste Lamarck, Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, and Henri Bergson.

The term orthogenesis was introduced by Wilhelm Haacke in 1893 and popularized by Theodor Eimer five years later. Proponents of orthogenesis had rejected the theory of natural selection as the organizing mechanism in evolution for a rectilinear model of directed evolution.[4] With the emergence of the modern synthesis, in which genetics was integrated with evolution, orthogenesis and other alternatives to Darwinism were largely abandoned by biologists, but the notion that evolution represents progress is still widely shared. The evolutionary biologist Ernst Mayr considered the term taboo in the journal Nature from 1948, as it implied "some supernatural force."[5][6] The American paleontologist George Gaylord Simpson (1953) attacked orthogenesis, linking it with vitalism by describing it as "the mysterious inner force".[7] Modern supporters include E. O. Wilson and Simon Conway Morris, while museum displays and textbook illustrations continue to give the impression of progress in evolution.

Definition

The term orthogenesis was first used by the biologist Wilhelm Haacke in 1893.[8][9] Theodor Eimer was the first to give the word a definition; he defined orthogenesis as "the general law according to which evolutionary development takes place in a noticeable direction, above all in specialized groups."[10]

In 1922, the zoologist Michael F. Guyer wrote:

[Orthogenesis] has meant many different things to many different people, ranging from a mystical inner perfecting principle, to merely a general trend in development due to the natural constitutional restrictions of the germinal materials, or to the physical limitations imposed by a narrow environment. In most modern statements of the theory, the idea of continuous and progressive change in one or more characters, due according to some to internal factors, according to others to external causes-evolution in a "straight line" seems to be the central idea.[11]

According to Susan R. Schrepfer in 1983:

Orthogenesis meant literally "straight origins", or "straight line evolution". The term varied in meaning from the overtly vitalistic and theological to the mechanical. It ranged from theories of mystical forces to mere descriptions of a general trend in development due to natural limitations of either the germinal material or the environment ... By 1910, however most who subscribed to orthogenesis hypothesized some physical rather than metaphysical determinant of orderly change.[12]

In 1988, Francisco J. Ayala defined progress as "systematic change in a feature belonging to all the members of a sequence in such a way that posterior members of the sequence exhibit an improvement of that feature." He argued that there are two elements in this definition, directional change and improvement according to some standard. Whether a directional change constitutes an improvement is not a scientific question; therefore Ayala suggested that science should focus on the question of whether there is directional change, without regard to whether the change is "improvement".[13] This may be compared to Stephen Jay Gould's suggestion of "replacing the idea of progress with an operational notion of directionality".[14]

In 1989, Peter J. Bowler defined orthogenesis as:

Literally, the term means evolution in a straight line, generally assumed to be evolution that is held to a regular course by forces internal to the organism. Orthogenesis assumes that variation is not random but is directed towards fixed goals. Selection is thus powerless, and the species is carried automatically in the direction marked out by internal factors controlling variation.[1]

In 1996, Michael Ruse defined orthogenesis as "the view that evolution has a kind of momentum of its own that carries organisms along certain tracks".[15]

History

The mediaeval great chain of being as a staircase, implying the possibility of progress:[16] Ramon Lull's Ladder of Ascent and Descent of the Mind, 1305

Mediaeval

The possibility of progress is embedded in the mediaeval great chain of being, with a linear sequence of forms from lowest to highest. The concept, indeed, had its roots in Aristotle's biology, from insects that produced only a grub, to fish that laid eggs, and on up to animals with blood and live birth. The mediaeval chain, as in Ramon Lull's Ladder of Ascent and Descent of the Mind, 1305, added steps or levels above humans, with orders of angels reaching up to God at the top.[16]

Pre-Darwinian

The orthogenesis hypothesis had a significant following in the 19th century when evolutionary mechanisms such as Lamarckism were being proposed. The French zoologist Jean-Baptiste Lamarck (1744–1829) himself accepted the idea, and it had a central role in his theory of inheritance of acquired characteristics, the hypothesized mechanism of which resembled the "mysterious inner force" of orthogenesis. Orthogenesis was particularly accepted by paleontologists who saw in their fossils a directional change, and in invertebrate paleontology thought there was a gradual and constant directional change. Those who accepted orthogenesis in this way, however, did not necessarily accept that the mechanism that drove orthogenesis was teleological (had a definite goal). Charles Darwin himself rarely used the term "evolution" now so commonly used to describe his theory, because the term was strongly associated with orthogenesis, as had been common usage since at least 1647.[17]

With Darwin

Reviewing Darwin's Origin of Species, Karl Ernst von Baer argued for a directed force guiding evolution.[18]

Ruse observed that "Progress (sic, his capitalisation) became essentially a nineteenth-century belief. It gave meaning to life—it offered inspiration—after the collapse [with Malthus's pessimism and the shock of the French revolution] of the foundations of the past."[19] The Russian biologist Karl Ernst von Baer (1792–1876) argued for an orthogenetic force in nature, reasoning in a review of Darwin's 1859 On the Origin of Species that "Forces which are not directed—so-called blind forces—can never produce order."[18][20][21] In 1864, the Swiss anatomist Albert von Kölliker (1817–1905) presented his orthogenetic theory, heterogenesis, arguing for wholly separate lines of descent with no common ancestor.[22] In 1884, the Swiss botanist Carl Nägeli (1817–1891) proposed a version of orthogenesis involving an "inner perfecting principle". Gregor Mendel died that same year; Nägeli, who proposed that an "idioplasm" transmitted inherited characteristics, dissuaded Mendel from continuing to work on plant genetics.[23] According to Nägeli many evolutionary developments were nonadaptive and variation was internally programmed. [1] Charles Darwin saw this as a serious challenge, replying that "There must be some efficient cause for each slight individual difference", but was unable to provide a specific answer without knowledge of genetics. Further, Darwin was himself somewhat progressionist, believing for example that "Man" was "higher" than the barnacles he studied.[24][25] Darwin indeed wrote in his 1859 Origin of Species:[26]

The inhabitants of each successive period in the world's history have beaten their predecessors in the race for life, and are, insofar, higher in the scale of nature; and this may account for that vague yet ill-defined sentiment, felt by many palaeontologists, that organisation on the whole has progressed. [Chapter 10][26]
As all the living forms of life are the lineal descendants of those which lived long before the Silurian epoch, we may feel certain that the ordinary succession by generation has never once been broken, and that no cataclysm has desolated the whole world. Hence we may look with some confidence to a secure future of equally inappreciable length. And as natural selection works solely by and for the good of each being, all corporeal and mental endowments will tend to progress towards perfection. [Chapter 14][26]

In 1898, after studying butterfly coloration, Theodor Eimer (1843–1898) introduced the term orthogenesis with a widely read book, On Orthogenesis: And the Impotence of Natural Selection in Species Formation. Eimer claimed there were trends in evolution with no adaptive significance that would be difficult to explain by natural selection.[27] To supporters of orthogenesis, in some cases species could be led by such trends to extinction.[28] Eimer linked orthogenesis to neo-Lamarckism in his 1890 book Organic Evolution as the Result of the Inheritance of Acquired Characteristics According to the Laws of Organic Growth. He used examples such as the evolution of the horse to argue that evolution had proceeded in a regular single direction that was difficult to explain by random variation. Gould described Eimer as a materialist who rejected any vitalist or teleological approach to orthogenesis, arguing that Eimer's criticism of natural selection was common amongst many evolutionists of his generation; they were searching for alternative mechanisms, as they had come to believe that natural selection could not create new species.[29]

Nineteenth and twentieth century

Henry Fairfield Osborn's 1934 version of orthogenesis, one of many, was called aristogenesis: he argued that aristogenes within the organism created all novelty, not mutation or natural selection.[30] Osborn supposed that the horns of Titanotheres evolved into a baroque form, way beyond the optimum that would have been adaptive.[31]

Numerous versions of orthogenesis (see table) have been proposed. Debate centred on whether such theories were scientific, or whether orthogenesis was inherently vitalistic or essentially theological.[32] For example, biologists such as Maynard M. Metcalf (1914), John Merle Coulter (1915), David Starr Jordan (1920) and Charles B. Lipman (1922) claimed evidence for orthogenesis in bacteria, fish populations and plants.[33][34][35][36] In 1950, the German paleontologist Otto Schindewolf argued that variation tends to move in a predetermined direction. He believed this was purely mechanistic, denying any kind of vitalism, but that evolution occurs due to a periodic cycle of evolutionary processes dictated by factors internal to the organism.[37][38] In 1964 George Gaylord Simpson argued that orthogenetic theories such as those promulgated by Du Noüy and Sinnott were essentially theology rather than biology.[32]

Though evolution is not progressive, it does sometimes proceed in a linear way, reinforcing characteristics in certain lineages, but such examples are entirely consistent with the modern neo-Darwinian theory of evolution.[39] These examples have sometimes been referred to as orthoselection but are not strictly orthogenetic, and simply appear as linear and constant changes because of environmental and molecular constraints on the direction of change.[40][41] The term orthoselection was first used by Ludwig Hermann Plate, and was incorporated into the modern synthesis by Julian Huxley and Bernard Rensch.[8]

Recent work has supported the mechanism and existence of mutation-biased adaptation, meaning that limited local orthogenesis is now seen as possible.[42][43][44]

Theories

For the columns for other philosophies of evolution (i.e., combined theories), "yes" means that person definitely supports the theory; "no" means explicit opposition to the theory; a blank means the matter is apparently not discussed, not part of the theory.

Theories of orthogenesis in evolutionary biology[45]
Author Title Field Date Lamarck. Mutat. Nat. Sel. Vital. Features
Lamarck Inherent progressive tendency Zoology 1809 yes In his Philosophie Zoologique, inherent progressive tendency drives organisms continuously towards greater complexity, in parallel but separate lineages, no extinction.[17] ("Lamarckism", use and disuse, and inheritance of acquired characteristics, was an aspect of this)
Baer Purposeful creation Embryology 1859 "Forces which are not directed—so-called blind forces—can never produce order."[18]
Kölliker Heterogenesis Anatomy 1864 yes Wholly separate lines of descent with no common ancestor[22]
Cope Law of acceleration Palaeontology 1868 yes Combined orthogenetic constraints with Lamarckian use and disuse. "On the Origin of Genera";[46][47][8] See also Cope's rule (linear increase in size of species)
Nägeli Inner perfecting principle Botany 1884 yes no An "idioplasm" transmitted inherited characteristics; many evolutionary developments nonadaptive; variation internally programmed.[1][8]
Darwin (concept of higher and lower species), Pangenesis Evolution 1859 yes yes Origin of Species is somewhat progressionist, e.g. man higher than animals, alongside natural selection[26][24] Pangenesis theory of inheritance by gemmules from all over body was Lamarckian: parents could pass on traits acquired in lifetime.[48][49]
Haacke Orthogenesis Zoology 1893 yes Accompanied by epimorphism, a tendency to increasing perfection[46][8]
Eimer Orthogenesis Zoology 1898 no On Orthogenesis: And the Impotence of Natural Selection in Species Formation: trends in evolution with no adaptive significance, claimed hard to explain by natural selection.[27][8]
Bergson Elan vital Philosophy 1907 yes Creative Evolution[50]
Przibram Apogenesis Embryology 1910s [46]
Plate Orthoselection or Old-Darwinism Zoology 1913 yes yes yes Combined theory[8]
Rosa Hologenesis Zoology 1918 yes Hologenesis: a New Theory of Evolution and the Geographical Distribution of Living Beings[51][8]
Whitman Orthogenesis Zoology 1919 no no no Orthogenetic Evolution in Pigeons posthumous[52][53]
Berg Nomogenesis Zoology 1926 no yes no Directed evolution leading to humans[54][8]
Abel Trägheitsgesetz (the law of inertia) Palaeontology 1928 based on Dollo's law of irreversibility of evolution (which can be explained without orthogenesis as a statistical improbability that a path should be exactly reversed)[8]
Lwoff Physiological degradation Physiology 1930s–1940s yes Directed loss of functions in microorganisms[46][55][56]
Beurlen Orthogenesis Palaeontology 1930 no no Start is random metakinesis, generating variety; then palingenesis (in Beurlen's sense, repeating developmental pathway of ancestors) as mechanism for orthogenesis[8]
Victor Jollos Directed mutation Protozoology, Zoology 1931 yes Combined orthogenesis with Lamarckism (inheriting acquired characteristics after heat shock as dauermodifications, passed on by plasmatic inheritance in the cytoplasm)[8]
Osborn Aristogenesis Palaeontology 1934 yes no no [30][57]
Willis Differentiation (orthogenesis) Botany 1942 yes a force "working upon some definite law that we do not yet comprehend"[58]
Noüy Telefinalism Biophysics 1947 yes In book Human Destiny,[59] essentially religious[59]
Vandel Organicism Zoology 1949 L'Homme et L'Evolution[46]
Sinnott Telism Botany 1950 yes In book Cell and Psyche,[59] essentially religious[32]
Schindewolf Typostrophism Palaeontology 1950 yes Basic Questions in Paleontology: Geologic Time, Organic Evolution and Biological Systematics; evolution due to periodic cycle of processes dictated by factors internal to organism.[37][8]
Teilhard de Chardin Directed additivity,
Noogenesis
Omega principle
Palaeontology
Mysticism
1959 yes The Phenomenon of Man posthumous; combined orthogenesis with non-material vitalist directive force aiming for a supposed "Omega Point" with creation of consciousness. Noosphere concept from Vladimir Vernadsky.[8] Censured by Gaylord Simpson for nonscientific spiritualistic "doubletalk".[10][60][61]
Croizat Biological synthesis
Panbiogeography
Botany 1964 mechanistic, caused by developmental constraints or phylogenetic constraints[46][62]
Multiple explanations have been offered since the 19th century for how evolution took place, given that many scientists initially had objections to natural selection. Many of these theories led to some form of orthogenesis, with or without invoking divine control directly or indirectly. For example, evolutionists like Edward Drinker Cope believed in a combination of theistic evolution, Lamarckism, vitalism, and orthogenesis,[63] represented by the sequence of arrows on the extreme left of the diagram.

The various alternatives to Darwinian evolution by natural selection were not necessarily mutually exclusive. The evolutionary philosophy of the American palaeontologist Edward Drinker Cope is a case in point. Cope, a religious man, began his career denying the possibility of evolution. In the 1860s, he accepted that evolution could occur, but, influenced by Agassiz, rejected natural selection. Cope accepted instead the theory of recapitulation of evolutionary history during the growth of the embryo - that ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny, which Agassiz believed showed a divine plan leading straight up to man, in a pattern revealed both in embryology and palaeontology. Cope did not go so far, seeing that evolution created a branching tree of forms, as Darwin had suggested. Each evolutionary step was however non-random: the direction was determined in advance and had a regular pattern (orthogenesis), and steps were not adaptive but part of a divine plan (theistic evolution). This left unanswered the question of why each step should occur, and Cope switched his theory to accommodate functional adaptation for each change. Still rejecting natural selection as the cause of adaptation, Cope turned to Lamarckism to provide the force guiding evolution. Finally, Cope supposed that Lamarckian use and disuse operated by causing a vitalist growth-force substance, "bathmism", to be concentrated in the areas of the body being most intensively used; in turn, it made these areas develop at the expense of the rest. Cope's complex set of beliefs thus assembled five evolutionary philosophies: recapitulationism, orthogenesis, theistic evolution, Lamarckism, and vitalism.[63] Other palaeontologists and field naturalists continued to hold beliefs combining orthogenesis and Lamarckism until the modern synthesis in the 1930s.[64]

Status

More extreme versions of the orthogenetic hypothesis began to lose popularity when it became clear that they were inconsistent with the patterns found by paleontologists in the fossil record, which were non-rectilinear (richly branching) with many complications. The hypothesis was abandoned by the mainstream of evolutionists when no mechanism could be found that would account for the process, and the theory of evolution by natural selection came to prevail.[65]

The modern synthesis of the 1930s and 1940s, in which the genetic mechanisms of evolution were incorporated, appeared to refute the hypothesis for good. As more was understood about these mechanisms it came to be held that there was no naturalistic way in which the newly discovered mechanism of heredity could be far-sighted or have a memory of past trends. Orthogenesis was seen to lie outside the methodological naturalism of the sciences.[66][67][68]

Ernst Mayr considered orthogenesis effectively taboo in 1948.[5]

By 1948, the evolutionary biologist Ernst Mayr, as editor of the journal Evolution, made the use of the term orthogenesis taboo: "It might be well to abstain from use of the word 'orthogenesis' .. since so many of the geneticists seem to be of the opinion that the use of the term implies some supernatural force."[5][6] With the rise of evolutionary developmental biology in the late 20th-early 21st centuries, however, which is open to an expanded concept of heredity that incorporates the physics of self-organization, ideas of constraint and preferred directions of morphological change have made a reappearance in evolutionary theory.[69]

For these and other reasons, belief in evolutionary progress has remained "a persistent heresy",[46] among evolutionary biologists including E. O. Wilson[70] and Simon Conway Morris, although often denied or veiled. The philosopher of biology Michael Ruse wrote that "some of the most significant of today's evolutionists are progressionists, and that because of this we find (absolute) progressionism alive and well in their work."[71] He argued that progressionism has harmed the status of evolutionary biology as a mature, professional science.[72] Presentations of evolution remain characteristically progressionist, with humans at the top of the "Tower of Time" in the Smithsonian Institution in Washington D.C., while Scientific American magazine could illustrate the history of life leading progressively from mammals to dinosaurs to primates and finally man. Ruse noted that at the popular level, progress and evolution are simply synonyms, as they were in the nineteenth century, though confidence in the value of cultural and technological progress has declined.[3]

Scientists, Ruse argues, continue to slide easily from one notion of progress to another: even committed Darwinians like Richard Dawkins embed the idea of cultural progress in a theory of cultural units, memes, that act much like genes.[3] Dawkins can speak of "progressive rather than random ... trends in evolution".[73][74] Dawkins and John Krebs deny the "earlier [Darwinian] prejudice"[75] that there is anything "inherently progressive about evolution",[76][75] but the feeling of progress comes from evolutionary arms races which remain in Dawkins's words "by far the most satisfactory explanation for the existence of the advanced and complex machinery that animals and plants possess".[77][75]

Ruse concludes his detailed analysis of the idea of "Progress" (with a capital letter, meaning a progressionist philosophy) in evolutionary biology by stating that evolutionary thought came out of that philosophy. Before Darwin, Ruse argues, evolution was just a pseudoscience; Darwin made it respectable, but "only as popular science". "There it remained frozen, for nearly another hundred years",[3] until mathematicians such as Fisher[78] provided "both models and status", enabling evolutionary biologists to construct the modern synthesis of the 1930s and 1940s. That made biology a professional science, at the price of ejecting the notion of progress. That, Ruse argues, was a significant cost to "people [biologists] still firmly committed to Progress" as a philosophy.[3]

Facilitated variation

Different species of Heliconius butterfly have independently evolved similar patterns, apparently both facilitated and constrained by the available developmental-genetic toolkit genes controlling wing pattern formation.

Biology has largely rejected the idea that evolution is guided in any way, but it appears that the evolution of some features is indeed facilitated by the genes of the developmental-genetic toolkit studied in evolutionary developmental biology. An example is the development of wing pattern in some species of Heliconius butterfly, which have independently evolved similar patterns. These butterflies are Müllerian mimics of each other, so natural selection is the driving force, but their wing patterns, which arose in separate evolutionary events, are controlled by the same genes.[79]

See also

References

  1. 1 2 3 4 Bowler 1989, pp. 268–270.
  2. Mayr, Ernst (1988). Toward a New Philosophy of Biology: Observations of an Evolutionist. Harvard University Press. p. 499. ISBN 0-674-89666-1.
  3. 1 2 3 4 5 Ruse 1996, pp. 526–539.
  4. Ulett, Mark A. (2014). "Making the case for orthogenesis: The popularization of definitely directed evolution (1890–1926)". Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences. 45: 124–132.
  5. 1 2 3 Ruse 1996, p. 447.
  6. 1 2 Letter from Ernst Mayr to R. H. Flower, Evolution papers, 23 January 1948
  7. Simpson, George Gaylord (1953). Life of the Past: An Introduction to Paleontology. Yale University Press. p. 125.
  8. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 Levit, Georgy S.; Olsson, Lennart (2006). "'Evolution on Rails' : Mechanisms and Levels of Orthogenesis" (PDF). Annals of the History and Philosophy of Biology (11): 99–138.
  9. Gould, Stephen Jay (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Harvard University Press. pp. 351–352. ISBN 978-0-674-00613-3.
  10. 1 2 Lane, David H. (1996). The Phenomenon of Teilhard: Prophet for a New Age. Mercer University Press. pp. 60–64. ISBN 0-86554-498-0.
  11. Guyer, Michael F. (1922). "Orthogenesis and Serological Phenomena". The American Naturalist. 56 (643): 116–133. JSTOR 2456504.
  12. Schrepfer, Susan R. (1983). Fight to Save the Redwoods: A History of the Environmental Reform, 1917–1978. University of Wisconsin Press. pp. 81–82. ISBN 978-0-299-08854-5.
  13. Ayala, Francisco J. (1988). Nitecki, M., ed. Can progress be defined as a biological concept?. Evolutionary Progress. University of Chicago Press. pp. 75–96. ISBN 0-226-58693-6.
  14. Gould, Stephen Jay (1997). Full House: The Spread of Excellence from Plato to Darwin. Harmony. ISBN 0-609-80140-6.
  15. Ruse 1996, p. 261.
  16. 1 2 Ruse 1996, pp. 21–23.
  17. 1 2 Gould, Stephen Jay (1977). Darwin's Dilemma: The Odyssey of Evolution. Ever Since Darwin: Reflections in Natural History. W. W. Norton. ISBN 0-393-06425-5. Archived from the original on 2005-12-16.
  18. 1 2 3 Brown, Keven; Von Kitzing, Eberhard (2001). Evolution and Bahá'í Belief: ʻAbduʼl-Bahá's Response to Nineteenth-century Darwinism. Kalimat Press. p. 159. ISBN 978-1-890688-08-0.
  19. Ruse 1996, p. 29.
  20. Barbieri, Marcello (2013). Biosemiotics: Information, Codes and Signs in Living Systems. Nova Science Publishers. p. 7. ISBN 978-1-60021-612-1.
  21. Jacobsen, Eric Paul (2005). From Cosmology to Ecology: The Monist World-view in Germany from 1770 to 1930. Peter Lang. p. 100. ISBN 978-0-8204-7231-7.
  22. 1 2 Vucinich, Alexander (1988). Darwin in Russian Thought. University of California Press. p. 137. ISBN 0-520-06283-3.
  23. Mawer, Simon (2006). Gregor Mendel: planting the seeds of genetics. Harry N. Abrams. ISBN 978-0-8109-5748-0.
  24. 1 2 Watson, Marc; Angle, Barbara (2017). Man's Selection: Charles Darwin's Theory of Creation, Evolution, And Intelligent Design. BookBaby. pp. 146–150. ISBN 978-1-936883-14-1.
  25. Ruse 1996, pp. 154–155, 162.
  26. 1 2 3 4 Darwin, C. (1859). On the Origin of Species By Means of Natural Selection, or, the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. Chapters 10, 14
  27. 1 2 Shanahan, Timothy (2004). The Evolution of Darwinism: Selection, Adaptation, and Progress in Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge University Press. p. 121. ISBN 978-0-521-54198-5.
  28. Sapp, Jan (2003). Genesis: The Evolution of Biology. Oxford University Press. pp. 69–70. ISBN 978-0-19-515619-5.
  29. Gould, Stephen Jay (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Harvard University Press. pp. 355–364. ISBN 978-0-674-00613-3.
  30. 1 2 Wallace, David Rains (2005). Beasts of Eden: Walking Whales, Dawn Horses, And Other Enigmas of Mammal Evolution. University of California Press. p. 96. ISBN 978-0-520-24684-3.
  31. Ruse 1996, pp. 266–267.
  32. 1 2 3 Simpson, George Gaylord (1964). "Evolutionary Theology: The New Mysticism". This View of Life: The World of an Evolutionist. Harcourt, Brace & World. pp. 213–233.
  33. Maynard M. Metcalf. (1913). Adaptation Through Natural Selection and Orthogenesis. The American Naturalist. Vol. 47, No. 554. pp. 65–71.
  34. John Merle Coulter. (1915). A Suggested Explanation of 'Orthogenesis' in Plants. Science, Vol. 42, No. 1094. pp. 859–863.
  35. David Starr Jordan. (1920). Orthogenesis among Fishes. Science, Vol. 52, No. 1331. pp. 13–14.
  36. Charles B. Lipman. (1922). Orthogenesis in Bacteria. The American Naturalist. Vol. 56, No. 643. pp. 105–115.
  37. 1 2 Kwa, Chunglin (2011). Styles of Knowing: A New History of Science from Ancient Times to the Present. University of Pittsburgh Press. p. 237. ISBN 978-0-8229-6151-2.
  38. Dimichele, William A. (1995). Basic Questions in Paleontology: Geologic Time, Organic Evolution, and Biological Systematics, by Otto H. Schindewolf. Review of Palaeobotany and Palynology 84. 481–483.
  39. Jepsen, Glenn L. (1949). "Selection. Orthogenesis, and the Fossil Record". Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society. 93 (6): 479–500.
  40. Jacobs, Susan C.; Larson, Allan; Cheverud, James M. (1995). "Phylogenetic Relationships and Orthogenetic Evolution of Coat Color Among Tamarins (Genus Saguinus)". Syst. Biol. 44 (4): 515–532.
  41. Ranganath, H. A.; Hägel, K. (1981). "Karyotypic orthoselection in Drosophila". Natur Wissenschaften. 68 (10): 527–528.
  42. Yampolsky, L. Y.; Stoltzfus, A. (2001). "Bias in the introduction of variation as an orienting factor in evolution". Evol Dev. 3 (2): 73–83. PMID 11341676. doi:10.1046/j.1525-142x.2001.003002073.x.
  43. Stoltzfus, A. (2006). Mutation-Biased Adaptation in a Protein NK Model. Mol Biol Evol. 23. pp. 1852–1862.
  44. Stoltzfus, A; Yampolsky, L. Y. (2009). "Climbing Mount Probable: Mutation as a Cause of Nonrandomness in Evolution". J Hered. 100 (5): 637–647. PMID 19625453. doi:10.1093/jhered/esp048.
  45. Cigna, Arrigo A.; Durante, Marco, ed. (2007). Radiation Risk Estimates in Normal and Emergency Situations. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 213. ISBN 978-1-4020-4956-9.
  46. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 Popov, Igor (7 April 2005). "The Persistence of Heresy: The Concepts of Directed Evolution (Orthogenesis)". Retrieved 15 April 2017.
  47. Barnes, M. Elizabeth (24 July 2014). "Edward Drinker Cope's Law of Acceleration of Growth".
  48. Ghiselin, Michael T. (September–October 1994). "Nonsense in schoolbooks: 'The Imaginary Lamarck'". The Textbook Letter. The Textbook League. Retrieved 2008-01-23.
  49. Magner, Lois N. (2002). A History of the Life Sciences (Third ed.). Marcel Dekker, CRC Press. ISBN 978-0-203-91100-6.
  50. Bowler 1989, pp. 116–117.
  51. Luzzatto, Michele; Palestrini, Claudia; D'entrèves, Passerin Pietro (2000). "Hologenesis: The Last and Lost Theory of Evolutionary Change". Italian Journal of Zoology. 67: 129–138.
  52. Castle, W.E. (1920). "Review of Orthogenetic Evolution in Pigeons". The American Naturalist. 54 (631): 188–192. doi:10.1086/279751.
  53. Gould, Stephen Jay (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Harvard University Press. p. 283. ISBN 978-0-674-00613-3.
  54. Ruse 1996, p. 395.
  55. Lwoff, A. (1944). L'evolution physiologique. Etude des pertes de fonctions chez les microorganismes. Paris: Hermann. pp. 1–308. L'idée s'imposa que les microorganismes avaient subi des pertes de fonction. Celles-ci apparurent comme la manifestation d'une évolution physiologique, definie comme une degradation, une orthogenese regressive.
  56. Loison, Laurent; Gayon, Jean; Burian, Richard M. (2017). "The Contributions – and Collapse – of Lamarckian Heredity in Pasteurian Molecular Biology: 1. Lysogeny, 1900–1960". Journal of the History of Biology. 50 (5): 5–52. doi:10.1007/s10739-015-9434-3.
  57. Regal, Brian (2002). Henry Fairfield Osborn: Race, and the Search for the Origins of Man. Ashgate. pp. 184–192. ISBN 978-0-7546-0587-4.
  58. The Course of Evolution by J. C. Willis. Review by: Carl L. Hubbs. The American Naturalist, Vol. 76, No. 762 (Jan. Feb., 1942), pp. 96–101.
  59. 1 2 3 Koch, Leo Francis (1957). "Vitalistic-Mechanistic Controversy". The Scientific Monthly. 85 (5): 245–255.
  60. Chardin, Pierre Teilhard de. (2003) [1959] The Human Phenomenon. Sussex Academic Press. p. 65. ISBN 1-902210-30-1
  61. Novack, George (2002). Marxist Writings on History & Philosophy. Resistance Books. p. 207. ISBN 978-1-876646-23-3.
  62. Gray, Russell (1989). "Oppositions in panbiogeography: can the conflicts between selection, constraint, ecology, and history be resolved?". New Zealand Journal of Zoology. 16: 787–806.
  63. 1 2 Bowler 1989, pp. 261-262.
  64. Bowler 1989, p. 264.
  65. Mayr, Ernst (1982). The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution, and Inheritance. Harvard University Press. pp. 530–531. ISBN 0-674-36446-5.
  66. Gould, Stephen Jay (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. pp. Chapter 7, section "Synthesis as Restriction". ISBN 0-674-00613-5.
  67. Levinton, Jeffrey S. (2001). Genetics, Paleontology, and Macroevolution. Cambridge University Press. pp. 14–16. ISBN 0-521-80317-9.
  68. Montgomery, Georgina M.; Largent, Mark A. (2015). A Companion to the History of American Science. Wiley. p. 218. ISBN 978-1-4051-5625-7. With the integration of Mendelian genetics and population genetics into evolutionary theory in the 1930s a new generation of biologists applied mathematical techniques to investigate how changes in the frequency of genes in populations combined with natural selection could produce species change. This demonstrated that Darwinian natural selection was the primary mechanism for evolution and that other models of evolution, such as neo-Lamarckism and orthogenesis, were invalid.
  69. see, for example, Müller, Gerd B.; Newman, Stuart A., ed. (2003). Origination of Organismal Form. Bradford. ISBN 0-262-13419-5.
  70. Ruse, Michael (31 March 2010). "Edward O. Wilson on Sociobiology". The Chronicle of Higher Education. Retrieved 4 April 2017.
  71. Ruse 1996, p. 536.
  72. Ruse 1996, p. 530.
  73. Dawkins, Richard; Krebs, J. R. (1979). "Arms races between and within species". Proc Royal Society B. 205: 489–511.
  74. Ruse 1996, p. 466.
  75. 1 2 3 Ruse 1996, p. 468.
  76. Dawkins 1986, p. 178.
  77. Dawkins 1986, p. 181.
  78. Ruse 1996, pp. 292–295.
  79. Baxter, S.W.; Papa, R.; Chamberlain, N.; Humphray, S.J.; Joron, M.; Morrison, C.; ffrench-Constant, R.H.; McMillan, W.O.; Jiggins, C.D. (2008). "Convergent Evolution in the Genetic Basis of Mullerian Mimicry in Heliconius Butterflies". Genetics. 180 (3): 1567–1577. PMC 2581958Freely accessible. PMID 18791259. doi:10.1534/genetics.107.082982.

Sources

Further reading


This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.