Solon
Solon (Greek: Σόλων; c. 638 – c. 558 BC) was an Athenian statesman, lawmaker, and poet. He is remembered particularly for his efforts to legislate against political, economic, and moral decline in archaic Athens.[1] His reforms failed in the short term, yet he is often credited with having laid the foundations for Athenian democracy.[2][3][4] He wrote poetry for pleasure, as patriotic propaganda, and in defense of his constitutional reforms.
Modern knowledge of Solon is limited by the fact that his works only survive in fragments and appear to feature interpolations by later authors, and by the general paucity of documentary and archaeological evidence covering Athens in the early 6th century BC.[5] Ancient authors such as Herodotus and Plutarch are the main source of information, yet they wrote about Solon long after his death, at a time when history was by no means an academic discipline. Fourth century orators, such as Aeschines, tended to attribute to Solon all the laws of their own, much later times.[1][6]
Biography
Solon was born in Athens around 638 B.C.[7] His family was distinguished in Attica as they belonged to a noble or Eupatrid clan although only possessing moderate wealth.[8] Solon's father probably was Execestides. Solon's lineage, therefore, could be traced back to Codrus, the last King of Athens.[9] According to Diogenes Laërtius, he had a brother named Dropides who was an ancestor (six generations removed) of Plato.[10] According to Plutarch, Solon was related to the tyrant Peisistratos for their mothers were cousins.[11] Solon was eventually drawn into the unaristocratic pursuit of commerce.[12]
When Athens and Megara were contesting for the possession of the Salamis Island, Solon was given leadership of the Athenian forces. After repeated disasters, Solon was able to increase the morale and spirits of his body of troops on the strength of a poem he wrote about the islands.[7] Supported by Peisistratos, he defeated the Megarians either by means of a cunning trick[13] or more directly through heroic battle around 595 B.C.[7][14] The Megarians however refused to give up their claim to the island. The dispute was referred to the Spartans, who eventually awarded possession of the island to Athens on the strength of the case that Solon put to them.[15]
According to Diogenes Laertius, in 594 B.C. Solon was chosen archon or chief magistrate.[7][16] As archon, Solon discussed his intended reforms with some friends. Knowing that he was about to cancel all debts, these friends took out loans and promptly bought some land. Suspected of complicity, Solon complied with his own law and released his own debtors, amounting to 5 talents (or 15 according to some sources). His friends never repaid their debts.[17]
After he had finished his reforms, he travelled abroad for ten years, so that the Athenians could not induce him to repeal any of his laws.[18] His first stop was Egypt. There, according to Herodotus he visited the Pharaoh of Egypt Amasis II.[19] According to Plutarch, he spent some time and discussed philosophy with two Egyptian priests, Psenophis of Heliopolis and Sonchis of Sais.[20] According to Plato's dialogues Timaeus and Critias, he visited Neith's temple at Sais and received from the priests there an account of the history of Atlantis. Next Solon sailed to Cyprus, where he oversaw the construction of a new capital for a local king, in gratitude for which the king named it Soloi.[20]
Solon's travels finally brought him to Sardis, capital of Lydia. According to Herodotus and Plutarch, he met with Croesus and gave the Lydian king advice, which however Croesus failed to appreciate until it was too late. Croesus had considered himself to be the happiest man alive and Solon had advised him, "Count no man happy until he be dead." The reasoning was that at any minute, fortune might turn on even the happiest man and make his life miserable. It was only after he had lost his kingdom to the Persian king Cyrus, while awaiting execution, that Croesus acknowledged the wisdom of Solon's advice.[21][22]
After his return to Athens, Solon became a staunch opponent of Peisistratos. In protest and as an example to others, Solon stood outside his own home in full armour, urging all who passed to resist the machinations of the would-be tyrant. His efforts were in vain. Solon died shortly after Peisistratos usurped by force the autocratic power that Athens had once freely bestowed upon him.[23] He died in Cyprus at the age of 80[7] and, in accordance with his will, his ashes were scattered around Salamis, the island where he was born.[24][25]
The travel writer Pausanias listed Solon among the seven sages whose aphorisms adorned Apollo's temple in Delphi.[26] Stobaeus in the Florilegium relates a story about a symposium, where Solon's young nephew was singing a poem of Sappho's; Solon, upon hearing the song, asked the boy to teach him to sing it. When someone asked, "Why should you waste your time on it?" Solon replied ἵνα μαθὼν αὐτὸ ἀποθάνω, "So that I may learn it then die."[27] Ammianus Marcellinus however told a similar story about Socrates and the poet Stesichorus, quoting the philosopher's rapture in almost identical terms: "ut aliquid sciens amplius e vita discedam",[28] meaning "in order to go away knowing more out of life".
Background to Solon's reforms
During Solon's time, many Greek city-states had seen the emergence of tyrants, opportunistic noblemen who had taken power on behalf of sectional interests. In Sicyon, Cleisthenes had usurped power on behalf of an Ionian minority. In Megara, Theagenes had come to power as an enemy of the local oligarchs. The son-in-law of Theagenes, an Athenian nobleman named Cylon, made an unsuccessful attempt to seize power in Athens in 632 BC. Solon was described by Plutarch as having been temporarily awarded autocratic powers by Athenian citizens on the grounds that he had the "wisdom" to sort out their differences for them in a peaceful and equitable manner.[29] According to ancient sources,[30][31] he obtained these powers when he was elected eponymous archon (594/3 BC). Some modern scholars believe these powers were in fact granted some years after Solon had been archon, when he would have been a member of the Areopagus and probably a more respected statesman by his (aristocratic) peers.[32][33][34]
The social and political upheavals that characterised Athens in Solon's time have been variously interpreted by historians from ancient times to the present day. Two contemporary historians have identified three distinct historical accounts of Solon's Athens, emphasizing quite different rivalries: economic and ideological rivalry, regional rivalry and rivalry between aristocratic clans.[35][36] These different accounts provide a convenient basis for an overview of the issues involved.
- Economic and ideological rivalry is a common theme in ancient sources. This sort of account emerges from Solon's poems (e.g. see below Solon the reformer and poet), in which he casts himself in the role of a noble mediator between two intemperate and unruly factions. This same account is substantially taken up about three centuries later by the author of the Aristotelian Athenaion Politeia but with an interesting variation:
"...there was conflict between the nobles and the common people for an extended period. For the constitution they were under was oligarchic in every respect and especially in that the poor, along with their wives and children, were in slavery to the rich...All the land was in the hands of a few. And if men did not pay their rents, they themselves and their children were liable to be seized as slaves. The security for all loans was the debtor's person up to the time of Solon. He was the first people's champion."[37]
Here Solon is presented as a partisan in a democratic cause whereas, judged from the viewpoint of his own poems, he was instead a mediator between rival factions. A still more significant variation in the ancient historical account appears in the writing of Plutarch in the late 1st – early 2nd century AD:
"Athens was torn by recurrent conflict about the constitution. The city was divided into as many parties as there were geographical divisions in its territory. For the party of the people of the hills was most in favour of democracy, that of the people of the plain was most in favour of oligarchy, while the third group, the people of the coast, which preferred a mixed form of constitution somewhat between the other two, formed an obstruction and prevented the other groups from gaining control."[38] - Regional rivalry is a theme commonly found among modern scholars.[39][40][41][42]
"The new picture which emerged was one of strife between regional groups, united by local loyalties and led by wealthy landowners. Their goal was control of the central government at Athens and with it dominance over their rivals from other districts of Attika."[43]
Regional factionalism was inevitable in a relatively large territory such as Athens possessed. In most Greek city states, a farmer could conveniently reside in town and travel to and from his fields every day. According to Thucydides, on the other hand, most Athenians continued to live in rural settlements right up until the Peloponnesian War.[44] The effects of regionalism in a large territory could be seen in Laconia, where Sparta had gained control through intimidation and resettlement of some of its neighbours and enslavement of the rest. Attika in Solon's time seemed to be moving towards a similarly ugly solution with many citizens in danger of being reduced to the status of helots.[45] - Rivalry between clans is a theme recently developed by some scholars, based on an appreciation of the political significance of kinship groupings.[43][46][47][48][49][50] According to this account, bonds of kinship rather than local loyalties were the decisive influence on events in archaic Athens. An Athenian belonged not only to a phyle or tribe and one of its subdivisions, the phratry or brotherhood, but also to an extended family, clan or genos. It has been argued that these interconnecting units of kinship reinforced a hierarchic structure with aristocratic clans at the top.[35][51] Thus rivalries between aristocratic clans could engage all levels of society irrespective of any regional ties. In that case, the struggle between rich and poor was the struggle between powerful aristocrats and the weaker affiliates of their rivals or perhaps even with their own rebellious affiliates.
The historical account of Solon's Athens has evolved over many centuries into a set of contradictory stories or a complex story that might be interpreted in a variety of ways. As further evidence accumulates, and as historians continue to debate the issues, Solon's motivations and the intentions behind his reforms will continue to attract speculation.[52]
Solon's reforms
Solon's laws were inscribed on large wooden slabs or cylinders attached to a series of axles that stood upright in the Prytaneion.[53][54] These axones appear to have operated on the same principle as a Lazy Susan, allowing both convenient storage and ease of access. Originally the axones recorded laws enacted by Draco in the late 7th Century (traditionally 621 BC). Nothing of Draco's codification has survived except for a law relating to homicide, yet there is consensus among scholars that it did not amount to anything like a constitution.[55][56] Solon repealed all Draco's laws except those relating to homicide.[57] During his visit to Athens, Pausanias, the 2nd century AD geographer reported that the inscribed laws of Solon were still displayed by the Prytaneion.[58] Fragments of the axones were still visible in Plutarch's time[59] but today the only records we have of Solon's laws are fragmentary quotes and comments in literary sources such as those written by Plutarch himself. Moreover, the language of his laws was archaic even by the standards of the fifth century and this caused interpretational problems for ancient commentators.[60] Modern scholars doubt the reliability of these sources and our knowledge of Solon's legislation is therefore actually very limited in its details.
Generally, Solon's reforms appear to have been constitutional, economic and moral in their scope. This distinction, though somewhat artificial, does at least provide a convenient framework within which to consider the laws that have been attributed to Solon. Some short-term consequences of his reforms are considered at the end of the section.
Constitutional reform
Before Solon's reforms, the Athenian state was administered by nine archons appointed or elected annually by the Areopagus on the basis of noble birth and wealth.[61][62] The Areopagus comprised former archons and it therefore had, in addition to the power of appointment, extraordinary influence as a consultative body. The nine archons took the oath of office while ceremonially standing on a stone in the agora, declaring their readiness to dedicate a golden statue if they should ever be found to have violated the laws.[63][64] There was an assembly of Athenian citizens (the Ekklesia) but the lowest class (the Thetes) was not admitted and its deliberative procedures were controlled by the nobles.[65] There therefore seemed to be no means by which an archon could be called to account for breach of oath unless the Areopagus favoured his prosecution.
According to the Athenian Constitution, Solon legislated for all citizens to be admitted into the Ekklesia[66] and for a court (the Heliaia) to be formed from all the citizens.[67] The Heliaia appears to have been the Ekklesia, or some representative portion of it, sitting as a jury.[68][69] By giving common people the power not only to elect officials but also to call them to account, Solon appears to have established the foundations of a true republic. However some scholars have doubted whether Solon actually included the Thetes in the Ekklesia, this being considered too bold a move for any aristocrat in the archaic period.[70] Ancient sources[71][72] credit Solon with the creation of a Council of Four Hundred, drawn from the four Athenian tribes to serve as a steering committee for the enlarged Ekklesia. However, many modern scholars have doubted this also.[73][74]
There is consensus among scholars that Solon lowered the requirements—those that existed in terms of financial and social qualifications—which applied to election to public office. The Solonian constitution divided citizens into four political classes defined according to assessable property[66][75] a classification that might previously have served the state for military or taxation purposes only.[76] The standard unit for this assessment was one medimnos (approximately 12 gallons) of cereals and yet the kind of classification set out below might be considered too simplistic to be historically accurate.[77]
- Pentakosiomedimnoi
- valued at 500 medimnoi or more of cereals annually.
- eligible to serve as strategoi (generals or military governors)
- Hippeis
- Zeugitai
- Thetes
- valued up to 199 medimnoi annually or less
- manual workers or sharecroppers, they served voluntarily in the role of personal servant, or as auxiliaries armed for instance with the sling or as rowers in the navy.
According to the Athenian Constitution, only the pentakosiomedimnoi were eligible for election to high office as archons and therefore only they gained admission into the Areopagus.[78] A modern view affords the same privilege to the hippeis.[79] The top three classes were eligible for a variety of lesser posts and only the thetes were excluded from all public office.
Depending on how we interpret the historical facts known to us, Solon's constitutional reforms were either a radical anticipation of democratic government, or they merely provided a plutocratic flavour to a stubbornly aristocratic regime, or else the truth lies somewhere between these two extremes.[nb 1]
Economic reform
Solon's economic reforms need to be understood in the context of the primitive, subsistence economy that prevailed both before and after his time. Most Athenians were still living in rural settlements right up to the Peloponnesian War.[80] Opportunities for trade even within the Athenian borders were limited. The typical farming family, even in classical times, barely produced enough to satisfy its own needs.[81] Opportunities for international trade were minimal. It has been estimated that, even in Roman times, goods rose 40% in value for every 100 miles they were carried over land, but only 1.3% for the same distance were they carried by ship[82] and yet there is no evidence that Athens possessed any merchant ships until around 525 BC.[83] Until then, the narrow warship doubled as a cargo vessel. Athens, like other Greek city states in the 7th Century BC, was faced with increasing population pressures[84] and by about 525 BC it was able to feed itself only in 'good years'.[85]
Solon's reforms can thus be seen to have taken place at a crucial period of economic transition, when a subsistence rural economy increasingly required the support of a nascent commercial sector. The specific economic reforms credited to Solon are these:
- Fathers were encouraged to find trades for their sons; if they did not, there would be no legal requirement for sons to maintain their fathers in old age.[86]
- Foreign tradesmen were encouraged to settle in Athens; those who did would be granted citizenship, provided they brought their families with them.[87]
- Cultivation of olives was encouraged; the export of all other produce was prohibited.[88]
- Competitiveness of Athenian commerce was promoted through revision of weights and measures, possibly based on successful standards already in use elsewhere, such as Aegina or Euboia[89][90] or, according to the ancient account but unsupported by modern scholarship, Argos.[91]
It is generally assumed, on the authority of ancient commentators[91][92] that Solon also reformed the Athenian coinage. However, recent numismatic studies now lead to the conclusion that Athens probably had no coinage until around 560 BC, well after Solon's reforms.[93] Nevertheless, there are now reasons to suggest[94] that monetization had already begun before Solon's reforms. By early sixth century the Athenians were using silver in the form of a variety of bullion silver pieces for monetary payments.[95] Drachma and obol as a term of bullion value had already been adopted, although the corresponding standard weights were probably unstable.[96]
Solon's economic reforms succeeded in stimulating foreign trade. Athenian black-figure pottery was exported in increasing quantities and good quality throughout the Aegean between 600 BC and 560 BC, a success story that coincided with a decline in trade in Corinthian pottery.[97] The ban on the export of grain might be understood as a relief measure for the benefit of the poor. However, the encouragement of olive production for export could actually have led to increased hardship for many Athenians to the extent that it led to a reduction in the amount of land dedicated to grain. Moreover, an olive produces no fruit for the first six years[98] (but farmers' difficulty of lasting until payback may also give rise to a mercantilist argument in favour of supporting them through that, since the British case illustrates that 'One domestic policy that had a lasting impact was the conversion of "waste lands" to agricultural use. Mercantilists felt that to maximize a nation's power all land and resources had to be used to their utmost...'). The real motives behind Solon's economic reforms are therefore as questionable as his real motives for constitutional reform. Were the poor being forced to serve the needs of a changing economy, was the economy being reformed to serve the needs of the poor, or were Solon's policies the manifestation of a struggle taking place between poorer citizens and the aristocrats?
Moral reform
In his poems, Solon portrays Athens as being under threat from the unrestrained greed and arrogance of its citizens.[99] Even the earth (Gaia), the mighty mother of the gods, had been enslaved.[100] The visible symbol of this perversion of the natural and social order was a boundary marker called a horos, a wooden or stone pillar indicating that a farmer was in debt or under contractual obligation to someone else, either a noble patron or a creditor.[101] Up until Solon's time, land was the inalienable property of a family or clan[102] and it could not be sold or mortgaged. This was no disadvantage to a clan with large landholdings since it could always rent out farms in a sharecropping system. A family struggling on a small farm however could not use the farm as security for a loan even if it owned the farm. Instead the farmer would have to offer himself and his family as security, providing some form of slave labour in lieu of repayment. Equally, a family might voluntarily pledge part of its farm income or labour to a powerful clan in return for its protection. Farmers subject to these sorts of arrangements were loosely known as hektemoroi[103] indicating that they either paid or kept a sixth of a farm's annual yield.[104][105][106] In the event of 'bankruptcy', or failure to honour the contract stipulated by the horoi, farmers and their families could in fact be sold into slavery.
Solon's reform of these injustices was later known and celebrated among Athenians as the Seisachtheia (shaking off of burdens).[107][108] As with all his reforms, there is considerable scholarly debate about its real significance. Many scholars are content to accept the account given by the ancient sources, interpreting it as a cancellation of debts, while others interpret it as the abolition of a type of feudal relationship, and some prefer to explore new possibilities for interpretation.[4] The reforms included:
- annulment of all contracts symbolised by the horoi.[109]
- prohibition on a debtor's person being used as security for a loan.[107][108]
- release of all Athenians who had been enslaved.[109]
The removal of the horoi clearly provided immediate economic relief for the most oppressed group in Attica, and it also brought an immediate end to the enslavement of Athenians by their countrymen. Some Athenians had already been sold into slavery abroad and some had fled abroad to escape enslavement – Solon proudly records in verse the return of this diaspora.[110] It has been cynically observed, however, that few of these unfortunates were likely to have been recovered.[111] It has been observed also that the seisachtheia not only removed slavery and accumulated debt, it also removed the ordinary farmer's only means of obtaining further credit.[112]
The seisachtheia however was merely one set of reforms within a broader agenda of moral reformation. Other reforms included:
- the abolition of extravagant dowries.[113]
- legislation against abuses within the system of inheritance, specifically with relation to the epikleros (i.e. a female who had no brothers to inherit her father's property and who was traditionally required to marry her nearest paternal relative in order to produce an heir to her father's estate).[114]
- entitlement of any citizen to take legal action on behalf of another.[115][116]
- the disenfranchisement of any citizen who might refuse to take up arms in times of civil strife, a measure that was intended to counteract dangerous levels of political apathy.[117][118][119][120][121]
Demosthenes claimed that the city's subsequent golden age included "personal modesty and frugality" among the Athenian aristocracy.[122] Perhap Solon, by both personal example and legislated reform, established a precedent for this decorum. A heroic sense of civic duty later united Athenians against the might of the Persians. Perhaps this public spirit was instilled in them by Solon and his reforms. Also see Solon and Athenian sexuality.
Aftermath of Solon's reforms
After completing his work of reform, Solon surrendered his extraordinary authority and left the country. According to Herodotus[123] the country was bound by Solon to maintain his reforms for 10 years, whereas according to Plutarch[59] and the author of the Athenian Constitution[124] (reputedly Aristotle) the contracted period was instead 100 years. A modern scholar[125] considers the time-span given by Herodotus to be historically accurate because it fits the 10 years that Solon was said to have been absent from the country.[126] Within 4 years of Solon's departure, the old social rifts re-appeared, but with some new complications. There were irregularities in the new governmental procedures, elected officials sometimes refused to stand down from their posts and occasionally important posts were left vacant. It has even been said that some people blamed Solon for their troubles.[127] Eventually one of Solon's relatives, Peisistratos, ended the factionalism by force, thus instituting an unconstitutionally gained tyranny. In Plutarch's account, Solon accused Athenians of stupidity and cowardice for allowing this to happen.[128]
Poetry
Solon's verses have come down to us in fragmentary quotations by ancient authors such as Plutarch and Demosthenes[129] who used them to illustrate their own arguments. It is possible that some fragments have been wrongly attributed to him[130] and some scholars have detected interpolations by later authors.[131] He was also the first citizen of Athens to reference the goddess Athena (fr. 4.1-4).[132]
The literary merit of Solon's verse is generally considered unexceptional. Solon's poetry can be said to appear 'self-righteous' and 'pompous' at times[133] and he once composed an elegy with moral advice for a more gifted elegiac poet, Mimnermus. Most of the extant verses show him writing in the role of a political activist determined to assert personal authority and leadership and they have been described by the German classicist Wilamowitz as a "versified harangue" (Eine Volksrede in Versen).[134] According to Plutarch[135] however, Solon originally wrote poetry for amusement, discussing pleasure in a popular rather than philosophical way. Solon's elegiac style is said to have been influenced by the example of Tyrtaeus.[136] He also wrote iambic and trochaic verses which, according to one modern scholar,[137] are more lively and direct than his elegies and possibly paved the way for the iambics of Athenian drama.
Solon's verses are mainly significant for historical rather than aesthetic reasons, as a personal record of his reforms and attitudes. However, poetry is not an ideal genre for communicating facts and very little detailed information can be derived from the surviving fragments.[138] According to Solon the poet, Solon the reformer was a voice for political moderation in Athens at a time when his fellow citizens were increasingly polarized by social and economic differences:
πολλοὶ γὰρ πλουτεῦσι κακοί, ἀγαθοὶ δὲ πένονται:
ἀλλ' ἡμεῖς αὐτοῖς οὐ διαμειψόμεθα
τῆς ἀρετῆς τὸν πλοῦτον: ἐπεὶ τὸ μὲν ἔμπεδον αἰεί,
χρήματα δ' ἀνθρώπων ἄλλοτε ἄλλος ἔχει.
Some wicked men are rich, some good are poor;
We will not change our virtue for their store:
Virtue's a thing that none can take away,
But money changes owners all the day.[8]
Here translated by the English poet John Dryden, Solon's words define a 'moral high ground' where differences between rich and poor can be reconciled or maybe just ignored. His poetry indicates that he attempted to use his extraordinary legislative powers to establish a peaceful settlement between the country's rival factions:
ἔστην δ' ἀμφιβαλὼν κρατερὸν σάκος ἀμφοτέροισι:
νικᾶν δ' οὐκ εἴασ' οὐδετέρους ἀδίκως.
Before them both I held my shield of might
And let not either touch the other's right.[75]
His attempts evidently were misunderstood:
χαῦνα μὲν τότ' ἐφράσαντο, νῦν δέ μοι χολούμενοι
λοξὸν ὀφθαλμοῖς ὁρῶσι πάντες ὥστε δήϊον.
Formerly they boasted of me vainly; with averted eyes
Now they look askance upon me; friends no more but enemies.[139]
Solon gave voice to Athenian 'nationalism', particularly in the city state's struggle with Megara, its neighbour and rival in the Saronic Gulf. Plutarch professes admiration of Solon's elegy urging Athenians to recapture the island of Salamis from Megarian control.[13] The same poem was said by Diogenes Laërtius to have stirred Athenians more than any other verses that Solon wrote:
Let us go to Salamis to fight for the island
We desire, and drive away our bitter shame![140]
It is possible that Solon backed up this poetic bravado with true valour on the battlefield.[15]
Solon and Athenian sexuality
As a regulator of Athenian society, Solon, according to some authors, also formalized its sexual mores. According to a surviving fragment from a work ("Brothers") by the comic playwright Philemon,[141] Solon established publicly funded brothels at Athens in order to "democratize" the availability of sexual pleasure.[142] While the veracity of this comic account is open to doubt, at least one modern author considers it significant that in Classical Athens, three hundred or so years after the death of Solon, there existed a discourse that associated his reforms with an increased availability of heterosexual pleasure.[143]
Ancient authors also say that Solon regulated pederastic relationships in Athens; this has been presented as an adaptation of custom to the new structure of the polis.[144][145] According to various authors, ancient lawgivers (and therefore Solon by implication) drew up a set of laws that were intended to promote and safeguard the institution of pederasty and to control abuses against freeborn boys. In particular, the orator Aeschines cites laws excluding slaves from wrestling halls and forbidding them to enter pederastic relationships with the sons of citizens.[146] Accounts of Solon's laws by 4th century orators like Aeschines, however, are considered unreliable for a number of reasons;[6][147][148]
Attic pleaders did not hesitate to attribute to him (Solon) any law which suited their case, and later writers had no criterion by which to distinguish earlier from later works. Nor can any complete and authentic collection of his statutes have survived for ancient scholars to consult.[149]
Besides the alleged legislative aspect of Solon's involvement with pederasty, there were also suggestions of personal involvement. According to some ancient authors Solon had taken the future tyrant Peisistratos as his eromenos. Aristotle, writing around 330 BC, attempted to refute that belief, claiming that "those are manifestly talking nonsense who pretend that Solon was the lover of Peisistratos, for their ages do not admit of it," as Solon was about thirty years older than Peisistratos.[150] Nevertheless, the tradition persisted. Four centuries later Plutarch ignored Aristotle's skepticism[151] and recorded the following anecdote, supplemented with his own conjectures:
And they say Solon loved [Peisistratos]; and that is the reason, I suppose, that when afterwards they differed about the government, their enmity never produced any hot and violent passion, they remembered their old kindnesses, and retained "Still in its embers living the strong fire" of their love and dear affection.[152]
A century after Plutarch, Aelian also said that Peisistratos had been Solon's eromenos. Despite its persistence, however, it is not known whether the account is historical or fabricated. It has been suggested that the tradition presenting a peaceful and happy coexistence between Solon and Peisistratos was cultivated during the latter's dominion, in order to legitimize his own rule, as well as that of his sons. Whatever its source, later generations lent credence to the narrative.[153] Solon's presumed pederastic desire was thought in antiquity to have found expression also in his poetry, which is today represented only in a few surviving fragments.[154][155] The authenticity of all the poetic fragments attributed to Solon is however uncertain – in particular, pederastic aphorisms ascribed by some ancient sources to Solon have been ascribed by other sources to Theognis instead.[130]
See also
Notes
- ↑ "In all areas then it was the work of Solon which was decisive in establishing the foundations for the development of a full democracy."—Marylin B. Arthur, 'The Origins of the Western Attitude Toward Women', in Women in the Ancient World: The Arethusa Papers, John Patrick Sullivan (ed.), State University of New York (1984), page 30.
"In making their own evaluation of Solon, the ancient sources concentrated on what were perceived to be the democratic features of the constitution. But...Solon was given his extraordinary commission by the nobles, who wanted him to eliminate the threat that the position of the nobles as a whole would be overthrown."—Stanton, G.R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1990), p. 76.
References
- 1 2 Aristotle Politics 1273b 35–1274a 21
- ↑ Stanton, G.R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1990), p. 76.
- ↑ Andrews, A. Greek Society (Penguin 1967) 197
- 1 2 E. Harris, A New Solution to the Riddle of the Seisachtheia, in 'The Development of the Polis in Archaic Greece', eds. L. Mitchell and P. Rhodes (Routledge 1997) 103
- ↑ Stanton G.R. Athenian Politics c800–500 BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1990), pp. 1–5.
- 1 2 V. Ehrenberg, From Solon to Socrates: Greek History and Civilization, Routledge (1973) 71
- 1 2 3 4 5 Solon: Biography of Solon
- 1 2 Plutarch Solon 1 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#1
- ↑ "Solon" in Magill, Frank N. (ed)., The Ancient World: Dictionary of World Biography (Salem Press/Routledge, 1998), p. 1057.
- ↑ Diogenes Laërtius, The Lives and Opinions of Famous Philosophers, Book 3 "Plato", chapter 1.
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 1 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#1.
- ↑ Plutarch, Life of Solon, ch.2
- 1 2 Plutarch Solon 8 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#8
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 9 s:Lives/Solon#9
- 1 2 Plutarch Solon 9 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#9
- ↑ SOLON of Athens
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 15 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#15
- ↑ Herodotus, The Histories, Hdt. 1.29
- ↑ Herodotus, The Histories, Hdt. 1.30
- 1 2 Plutarch Solon 26 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#26
- ↑ Herodotus 1.30.
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 28 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#28
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 32 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#32
- ↑ Diogenes Laertius 1.62
- ↑ I. M. Linforth, Solon the Athenian, University of California press (1919), p.308, Google Books link
- ↑ Pausanias 10.24.1 (e.g. Jones and Omerod trans. ).
- ↑ Stobaeus, III, 29, 58, taken from a lost work of Aelian.
- ↑ Ammianus Marcellinus 38.4
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 14 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#14
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 14.3 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#14
- ↑ Athenaion Politeia 1.5 (e.g. Kenyon's translation s:Athenian Constitution#5)
- ↑ Stanton G.R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1990), p. 36.
- ↑ Hignett C. A History of the Athenian Constitution to the End of the Fifth Century B.C. (Oxford University Press 1952).
- ↑ Miller, M. Arethusa 4 (1971) 25–47.
- 1 2 Stanton G.R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1991), pp. 3–4.
- ↑ Walters, K.R., Geography and Kinship as Political Infrastructures in Archaic Athens
- ↑ Athenaion Politeia 2.1–2.3 s:Athenian Constitution#2.
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 13 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#13
- ↑ B. Sealey, "Regionalism in Archaic Athens," Historia 9 (1960) 155-180.
- ↑ D.Lewis, "Cleisthenes and Attica," Historia 12 (1963) 22-40.
- ↑ P. Rhodes, A Commentary on the Aristotelian Athenian Politeia, Oxford University Press (1981) 186.
- ↑ P. Rhodes, A History of the Greek City States, Berkeley (1976).
- 1 2 Walters K.R. Geography and Kinship as Political Infrastructures in Archaic Athens
- ↑ Thucydides 2.14 - 2.16.
- ↑ Andrews, A. Greek Society (Penguin 1967) 118.
- ↑ Stanton G.R. Athenian Politics c800-500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1991), pages 3-4.
- ↑ Frost, "Tribal Politics and the Civic State," AJAH (1976) 66-75.
- ↑ Connor, The New Politicians of Fifth Century Athens, Princeton (1971) 11-14.
- ↑ Cary, Cambridge Ancient History, Cambridge Univ. Press (1925) 3:582-586.
- ↑ Ellis, J. and Stanton, G., Phoenix 22 (1968) 95-99.
- ↑ Walters, K.R., Geography and Kinship as Political Infrastructures in Archaic Athens .
- ↑ See, for example, J. Bintliff, "Solon's Reforms: an archeological perspective", in Solon of Athens: new historical and philological approaches, eds. J. Blok and A. Lardinois (Brill, Leiden 2006), and other essays published with it.
- ↑ V. Ehrenberg, From Solon to Socrates: Greek History and Civilization, Routledge (1973) 71–72
- ↑ Stanton, G.R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1991), page 52
- ↑ Stanton, G.R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1990), page 26
- ↑ Oxford Classical Dictionary (1964), 'Draco'
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 17 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#17
- ↑ Pausanias, Description of Greece, 1.18.3
- 1 2 Plutarch Solon 25.1 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#25
- ↑ Andrews A. Greek Society (Penguin 1967) 114, 201
- ↑ Athenaion Politeia 3.6 s:Athenian Constitution#3
- ↑ Athenaion Politeia 8.2 s:Athenian Constitution#8
- ↑ Athenaion Politeia 7.1, 55.5 s:Athenian Constitution#7
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 25.3 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#25
- ↑ Stanton, G.R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1991), page 35, note 2
- 1 2 Athenaion Politeia 7.3 s:Athenian Constitution#7
- ↑ Aristotle Politics 1274a 3, 1274a 15
- ↑ Ostwald M. From Popular Sovereignty to the Sovereignty of the Law: Law, Society and Politics in Fifth Century Athens (Berkeley 1986) 9–12, 35.
- ↑ Stanton, G.R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1990), page 67 note 2
- ↑ Hignett C. A History of the Athenian Constitution to the End of the Fifth Century B.C. (Oxford University Press 1952) pages 117–118
- ↑ Athenaion Politeia 8.4 s:Athenian Constitution#8
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 19 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#19
- ↑ Hignett C. A History of the Athenian Constitution to the End of the Fifth Century B.C. (Oxford University Press 1952) 92–96
- ↑ Stanton, G.R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1990), page 72 note 14
- 1 2 Plutarch Solon 18 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#18
- ↑ Stanton, G.R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1990), page 71 note 6
- ↑ V. Ehrenberg, From Solon to Socrates: Greek History and Civilization, Routledge (1973)
- ↑ Athenaion Politeia 7–8 s:Athenian Constitution#7
- ↑ Oxford Classical Dictionary (3rd edition 1996) Solon
- ↑ Thucydides 2.14–2.16
- ↑ Gallant T. Risk and Survival in Ancient Greece (Stanford, 1991), cited by Morris I. in The Growth of City States in the First Millennium BC (Stanford, 2005) page 7
- ↑ Laurence R. Land Transport in Rural Italy (Parkins and Smith, 1998), cited by Morris I. in The Growth of City States in the First Millennium BC (Stanford, 2005)
- ↑ Morris I. The Growth of City States in the First Millennium BC (Stanford, 2005) page 12
- ↑ Snodgrass A. Archaic Greece (London, 1980) cited by Morris I. in The Growth of City States in the First Millennium BC (Stanford, 2005) page 11
- ↑ Garnsey P. Famine and Food Supply in Graeco-Roman World (Cambridge, 1988) page 104, cited by Morris I. in The Growth of City States in the First Millennium BC (Stanford, 2005)
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 22.1 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#22
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 24.4 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#24
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 24.1 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#24
- ↑ V. Ehrenberg, From Solon to Socrates: Greek History and Civilization, Routledge (1973) 73–74
- ↑ Stanton, G. R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1990), page 60–63
- 1 2 Athenaion Politeia 10 s:Athenian Constitution#10
- ↑ Plutarch (quoting Androtion) Solon 15.2–5 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#15
- ↑ Stanton, G. R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1990), page 61 note 4
- ↑ Eberhard Ruschenbusch 1966, Solonos Nomoi (Solon's laws)
- ↑ Kroll, 1998, 2001, 2008
- ↑ The Oxford Handbook of Greek and Roman Coinage by William Metcalf, page 88
- ↑ Stanton, G.R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1990), page 76
- ↑ Stanton, G.R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1991), page 65 note 1
- ↑ Demosthenes 19 (On the Embassy) 254–5
- ↑ Athenaion Politeia 12.4 (quoting Solon) s:Athenian Constitution#12
- ↑ Stanton, G. R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1991), pages 55–6 notes 3 and 4
- ↑ Innis H. Empire and Communications (Rowman and Littlefield, 2007) pages 91–92
- ↑ Stanton, G. R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1991), page 38 note 3
- ↑ Stanton, G. R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1990), page 35 note 3
- ↑ Kirk. G, Historia Vol. 26 (1977) 369–370
- ↑ Woodhouse W. Solon the Liberator: A Study of the Agrarian Problem in Attika in the Seventh Century (Oxford University Press 1938)
- 1 2 Athenaion Politeia 6 s:Athenian Constitution#6
- 1 2 Plutarch Solon 15.2 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#15
- 1 2 Athenaion Politeia 12.4, quoting Solon s:Athenian Constitution#12
- ↑ Solon quoted in Athenaion Politeia 12.4 s:Athenian Constitution#12
- ↑ Forrest G. The Oxford History of the Classical World ed Griffin J. and Murray O. (Oxford University Press, 1995) page 32
- ↑ Stanton, G. R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC; a Sourcebook Routledge, London (1991) page 57 note 1
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 20.6 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#20
- ↑ Grant, Michael. The Rise of the Greeks. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1988 p. 49
- ↑ Athenaion Politeia 9 s:Athenian Constitution#9
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 18.6 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#18
- ↑ Athenaion Politeia 8.5 s:Athenian Constitution#8
- ↑ Stanton, G. R. Athenian Politics c800–500BC; a Sourcebook Routledge, London (1991) page 72 note 17
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 20.1 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#20
- ↑ Goldstein J. Historia Vol. 21 (1972) 538–545.
- ↑ Develin R. Historia Vol. 26 (1977) 507–508.
- ↑ Demosthenes On Organization
- ↑ Herodotus 1.29 (e.g. Campbell's translation 2707)
- ↑ Athenaion Politeia 7.2 s:Athenian Constitution#7
- ↑ Stanton, G.R. Athenian Politics c800–55BC; a Sourcebook Routledge, London (1991) page 84
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 25.6 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#25
- ↑ Athenaion Politeia 13 s:Athenian Constitution#13
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 30 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#30
- ↑ Demosthenes 19 (On the Embassy) 254-5
- 1 2 K.Hubbard, Homosexuality in Greece and Rome: a sourcebook of basic documents, Uni. California Press, 2003; p.36
- ↑ A.Lardinois, Have we Solon's verses? and E.Stehle, Solon's self-reflexive political persona and its audience, in 'Solon of Athens: new historical and philological approaches', eds. J.Blok and A.Lardinois (Brill, Leiden 2006)
- ↑ Susan Deacy, Gods and Heroes of the Ancient World: Athena (2008) pg. 77
- ↑ Forrest G., The Oxford History of the Classical World, ed. Boardman J., Griffin J. and Murray O., Oxford University Press (New York, 1995), page 31
- ↑ Wilamowitz, Arist. u. Athen, ii 304, cited by Eduard Fraenkel, Horace, Oxford University Press (1957), page 38
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 3.1-4 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#3
- ↑ Oxford Classical Dictionary (1964) Solon
- ↑ David. A. Campbell, Greek Lyric Poetry, Bristol Classical Press 1982, Intro. xxix
- ↑ Andrews A. Greek Society (Penguin 1981) 114
- ↑ Plutarch Solon 16 s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon#16
- ↑ Solon, quoted in Diogenes Laërtius 1.47
- ↑ Fr. 4
- ↑ Rachel Adams, David Savran, The Masculinity Studies Reader; Blackwell, 2002; p.74
- ↑ One Hundred Years of Homosexuality: And Other Essays on Greek Love, p.101
- ↑ Bernard Sergent, "Paederasty and Political Life in Archaic Greek Cities" in Gay Studies from the French Culture; Harrington Park Press, Binghamton, NY 1993; pp.153–154
- ↑ Eros and Greek Athletics By Thomas Francis Scanlon, p.213 "So it is clear that Solon was responsible for institutionalizing pederasty to some extent at Athens in the early sixth century."
- ↑ Aeschines, Against Timarchus 6, 25, 26 ; compare also Plutarch, Solon 1.3.
- ↑ Kevin Robb, Literacy and Paideia in Ancient Greece, Ox. Uni. Press, 1994; p. 128,
- ↑ P. J. Rhodes, The Reforms and Laws of Solon: an Optimistic View, in 'Solon of Athens: new historical and philological approaches', eds. J. Blok and A. Lardinois (Brill, Leiden 2006)
- ↑ Kevin Robb, Literacy and Paideia in Ancient Greece, Ox. Uni. Press 1994; p. 128 (quoting F. E. Adcock)
- ↑ Aristotle, The Athenian Constitution, 2.17
- ↑ Homosexuality & Civilization By Louis Crompton, p. 25
- ↑ Plutarch, The Lives "Solon" Tr. John Dryden s:Lives (Dryden translation)/Solon
- ↑ Solon and Early Greek Poetry By Elizabeth Irwin p. 272 n. 24
- ↑ Ancient Greece By Matthew Dillon, Lynda Garland, p. 475
- ↑ Nick Fisher, Against Timarchos, Oxford University Press 2001, p. 37
Literature
- A. Andrews, Greek Society, Penguin, 1967
- J. Blok and A. Lardinois (eds), Solon of Athens: New Historical and Philological Approaches, Leiden, Brill, 2006
- Cary, Cambridge Ancient History, Vol. III, Cambridge Uni. Press, 1925
- Connor, The New Politicians of Fifth-Century Athens, Princeton, 1971
- W. Connor et al. Aspects of Athenian Democracy, Copenhagen, Museum Tusculanam P., 1990
- R. Develin, Historia, Vol. 26, 1977
- V. Ehrenberg, From Solon to Socrates: Greek History and Civilization, Routledge, 1973
- J. Ellis and G. Stanton, Phoenix, Vol. 22, 1968, 95-99
- G. Forrest, 'Greece: The History of the Archaic Period', in The Oxford History of the Classical World, ed. Boardman J., Griffin J. and Murray O., Oxford University Press, New York, 1995
- Frost, 'Tribal Politics and the Civic State', AJAH, 1976
- P. Garnsey, Famine and Food Supply in Graeco-Roman World, Cambridge Uni. Press, 1988
- J. Goldstein, Historia, Vol. 21, 1972
- M. Grant, The Rise of the Greeks. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1988
- E. Harris, 'A New Solution to the Riddle of the Seisachtheia', in The Development of the Polis in Archaic Greece, eds. L. Mitchell and P. Rhodes, Routledge, 1997
- C. Hignett, A History of the Athenian Constitution to the End of the Fifth Century B.C., Oxford University Press, 1952
- K. Hubbard, Homosexuality in Greece and Rome: a sourcebook of basic documents, Uni. California Press, 2003
- H. Innis, Empire and Communications, Rowman and Littlefield, 2007
- G. Kirk, Historia, Vol. 26, 1977
- D. Lewis, 'Cleisthenes and Attica', Historia, 12, 1963
- M. Miller, Arethusa, Vol. 4, 1971
- I. Morris, The Growth of City States in the First Millennium BC, Stanford, 2005
- C. Mosse, 'Comment s'elabore un mythe politique: Solon', Annales, ESC XXXIV, 1979
- M. Ostwald, From Popular Sovereignty to the Sovereignty of the Law: Law, Society and Politics in Fifth-Century Athens, Berkeley, 1986
- P. Rhodes, A History of the Greek City States, Berkeley, 1976
- P. Rhodes, A Commentary on the Aristotelian Athenian Politeia, Oxford University Press, 1981
- K. Robb, Literacy and Paideia in Ancient Greece, Oxford University Press, 1994
- B. Sealey, 'Regionalism in Archaic Athens', Historia, 9, 1960
- G. R. Stanton, Athenian Politics c. 800–500 BC: A Sourcebook, London, Routledge, 1990
- M. L. West (ed.), Iambi et elegi Graeci ante Alexandrum cantati2: Callinus. Mimnermus. Semonides. Solon. Tyrtaeus. Minora adespota, Oxford University Press: Clarendon Press, 1972, revised edition, 1992
- W. Woodhouse, 'Solon the Liberator: A Study of the Agrarian Problem', in Attika in the Seventh Century, Oxford University Press, 1938
Collections of Solon's surviving verses
- Martin Litchfield West, Iambi et elegi Graeci ante Alexandrum cantati2 : Callinus. Mimnermus. Semonides. Solon. Tyrtaeus. Minora adespota,, Oxonii: e typographeo Clarendoniano 1972, revised edition 1992 x + 246 pp.
- T. Hudaon-Williams, Early Greek Elegy: Ekegiac Fragments of Callinus, Archilochus, Mimmermus, Tyrtaeus, Solon, Xenophanes, and Others, # Taylor and Francis (1926), ISBN 0-8240-7773-3.
- Christoph Mülke, Solons politische Elegien und Iamben : (Fr. 1 - 13, 32 - 37 West), Munich (2002), ISBN 3-598-77726-4.
- Eberhard Ruschenbusch Nomoi : Die Fragmente d. Solon. Gesetzeswerkes, Wiesbaden : F. Steiner (1966).
- H. Miltner Fragmente / Solon, Vienna (1955)
- Eberhard Preime, Dichtungen : Sämtliche Fragmente / Solon Munich (1940).
External links
Wikiquote has quotations related to: Solon |
Wikimedia Commons has media related to Solon. |
- Plutarch, Parallel Lives, Solon
- Diogenes Laërtius, Life of Solon, translated by Robert Drew Hicks (1925).
- Poems of Solon
|
|
|
|