Logical consequence

"Entailment" redirects here. For other uses, see Entail (disambiguation).
"Therefore" redirects here. For the therefore symbol (∴), see Therefore sign.
"Logical implication" redirects here. For the binary connective, see Material conditional.

Logical consequence (also entailment) is one of the most fundamental concepts in logic. It is the relationship between statements that holds true when one logically "follows from" one or more others. A valid logical argument is one in which the conclusions follow from its premises, and its conclusions are consequences of its premises. The philosophical analysis of logical consequence involves asking, 'in what sense does a conclusion follow from its premises?' and 'what does it mean for a conclusion to be a consequence of premises?'[1] All of philosophical logic can be thought of as providing accounts of the nature of logical consequence, as well as logical truth.[2]

Logical consequence is taken to be both necessary and formal with examples explicated using models and proofs.[1] A sentence is said to be a logical consequence of a set of sentences, for a given language, if and only if, using logic alone (i.e. without regard to any interpretations of the sentences) the sentence must be true if every sentence in the set were to be true.[3]

Logicians make precise accounts of logical consequence with respect to a given language \mathcal{L} by constructing a deductive system for \mathcal{L}, or by formalizing the intended semantics for \mathcal{L}. Alfred Tarski highlighted three salient features for which any adequate characterization of logical consequence needs to account: 1) that the logical consequence relation relies on the logical form of the sentences involved, 2) that the relation is a priori, i.e. it can be determined whether or not it holds without regard to sense experience, and 3) that the relation has a modal component.[3]

Formal accounts

The most widely prevailing view on how to best account for logical consequence is to appeal to formality. This is to say that whether statements follow from one another logically depends on the structure or logical form of the statements without regard to the contents of that form.

Syntactic accounts of logical consequence rely on schemes using inference rules. For instance, we can express the logical form of a valid argument as "All A are B. All C are A. Therefore, All C are B." This argument is formally valid, because every instance of arguments constructed using this scheme are valid.

This is in contrast to an argument like "Fred is Mike's brother's son. Therefore Fred is Mike's nephew." Since this argument depends on the meanings of the words "brother", "son", and "nephew", the statement "Fred is Mike's nephew" is a so-called material consequence of "Fred is Mike's brother's son," not a formal consequence. A formal consequence must be true in all cases, however this is an incomplete definition of formal consequence, since even the argument "P is Q's brother's son, therefore P is Q's nephew" is valid in all cases, but is not a formal argument.[1]

A priori property of logical consequence

If you know that Q follows logically from P no information about the possible interpretations of P or Q will affect that knowledge. Our knowledge that Q is a logical consequence of P cannot be influenced by empirical knowledge.[1] Deductively valid arguments can be known to be so without recourse to experience, so they must be knowable a priori.[1] However, formality alone does not guarantee that logical consequence is not influenced by empirical knowledge. So the a priori property of logical consequence is considered to be independent of formality.[1]

Proofs and models

The two prevailing techniques for providing accounts of logical consequence involve expressing the concept in terms of proofs and via models. The study of the syntactic consequence (of a logic) is called (its) proof theory whereas the study of (its) semantic consequence is called (its) model theory.[4]

Syntactic consequence

See also: and

A formula A is a syntactic consequence[5][6][7][8] within some formal system \mathcal{FS} of a set \Gamma of formulas if there is a formal proof in \mathcal{FS} of A from the set \Gamma.

\Gamma \vdash_{\mathcal {FS} } A

Syntactic consequence does not depend on any interpretation of the formal system.[9]

Semantic consequence

See also:

A formula A is a semantic consequence within some formal system \mathcal{FS} of a set of statements \Gamma

\Gamma \models_{\mathcal {FS} } A,

if and only if there is no model \mathcal{I} in which all members of \Gamma are true and A is false.[10] Or, in other words, the set of the interpretations that make all members of \Gamma true is a subset of the set of the interpretations that make A true.

Modal accounts

Modal accounts of logical consequence are variations on the following basic idea:

\Gamma \vdash A is true if and only if it is necessary that if all of the elements of \Gamma are true, then A is true.

Alternatively (and, most would say, equivalently):

\Gamma \vdash A is true if and only if it is impossible for all of the elements of \Gamma to be true and A false.

Such accounts are called "modal" because they appeal to the modal notions of logical necessity and logical possibility. 'It is necessary that' is often expressed as a universal quantifier over possible worlds, so that the accounts above translate as:

\Gamma \vdash A is true if and only if there is no possible world at which all of the elements of \Gamma are true and A is false (untrue).

Consider the modal account in terms of the argument given as an example above:

All frogs are green.
Kermit is a frog.
Therefore, Kermit is green.

The conclusion is a logical consequence of the premises because we can't imagine a possible world where (a) all frogs are green; (b) Kermit is a frog; and (c) Kermit is not green.

Modal-formal accounts

Modal-formal accounts of logical consequence combine the modal and formal accounts above, yielding variations on the following basic idea:

\Gamma \vdash A if and only if it is impossible for an argument with the same logical form as \Gamma/A to have true premises and a false conclusion.

Warrant-based accounts

The accounts considered above are all "truth-preservational," in that they all assume that the characteristic feature of a good inference is that it never allows one to move from true premises to an untrue conclusion. As an alternative, some have proposed "warrant-preservational" accounts, according to which the characteristic feature of a good inference is that it never allows one to move from justifiably assertible premises to a conclusion that is not justifiably assertible. This is (roughly) the account favored by intuitionists such as Michael Dummett.

Non-monotonic logical consequence

Main article: Non-monotonic logic

The accounts discussed above all yield monotonic consequence relations, i.e. ones such that if A is a consequence of \Gamma, then A is a consequence of any superset of \Gamma. It is also possible to specify non-monotonic consequence relations to capture the idea that, e.g., 'Tweety can fly' is a logical consequence of

{Birds can typically fly, Tweety is a bird}

but not of

{Birds can typically fly, Tweety is a bird, Tweety is a penguin}.

For more on this, see Belief revision#Non-monotonic inference relation.

See also

Notes

  1. 1 2 3 4 5 6 Beall, JC and Restall, Greg, Logical Consequence The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2009 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.).
  2. Quine, Willard Van Orman, Philosophy of logic
  3. 1 2 McKeon, Matthew, Logical Consequence Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  4. Kosta Dosen (1996). "Logical consequence: a turn in style". In Maria Luisa Dalla Chiara, Kees Doets, Daniele Mundici, Johan van Benthem. Logic and Scientific Methods: Volume One of the Tenth International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Florence, August 1995. Springer. p. 292. ISBN 978-0-7923-4383-7.
  5. Dummett, Michael (1993) Frege: philosophy of language Harvard University Press, p.82ff
  6. Lear, Jonathan (1986) Aristotle and Logical Theory Cambridge University Press, 136p.
  7. Creath, Richard, and Friedman, Michael (2007) The Cambridge companion to Carnap Cambridge University Press, 371p.
  8. FOLDOC: "syntactic consequence"
  9. Hunter, Geoffrey, Metalogic: An Introduction to the Metatheory of Standard First-Order Logic, University of California Pres, 1971, p. 75.
  10. Etchemendy, John, Logical consequence, The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy

Resources

External links

This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the Monday, September 21, 2015. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.