Löb's theorem

In mathematical logic, Löb's theorem states that in a theory with Peano arithmetic, for any formula P, if it is provable that "if P is provable then P is true", then P is provable. I.e.

\mathrm{if}\ PA \vdash (Bew(\# P) \rightarrow P)\mathrm{, then}\ PA \vdash P

where Bew(#P) means that the formula P with Gödel number #P is provable (from the German "beweisbar").

Löb's theorem is named for Martin Hugo Löb, who formulated it in 1955.

Löb's theorem in provability logic

Provability logic abstracts away from the details of encodings used in Gödel's incompleteness theorems by expressing the provability of \phi in the given system in the language of modal logic, by means of the modality \Box \phi.

Then we can formalize Löb's theorem by the axiom

\Box(\Box P\rightarrow P)\rightarrow \Box P,

known as axiom GL, for Gödel-Löb. This is sometimes formalised by means of an inference rule that infers

 P

from

\Box P\rightarrow P.

The provability logic GL that results from taking the modal logic K4 (or K, since the axiom schema 4, \Box A\rightarrow\Box\Box A, then becomes redundant) and adding the above axiom GL is the most intensely investigated system in provability logic.

Modal Proof of Löb's theorem

Löb's theorem can be proved within modal logic using only some basic rules about the provability operator (the K4 system) plus the existence of modal fixed points.

Modal Formulas

We will assume the following grammar for formulas:

  1. If X is a propositional variable, then X is a formula.
  2. If K is a propositional constant, then K is a formula.
  3. If A is a formula, then \Box A is a formula.
  4. If A and B are formulas, then so are \neg A, A \rightarrow B, A \wedge B, A \vee B, and A \leftrightarrow B

A modal sentence is a modal formula that contains no propositional variables. We use \vdash A to mean A is a theorem.

Modal Fixed Points

If F(X) is a modal formula with only one propositional variable X, then a modal fixed point of F(X) is a sentence \Psi such that

\vdash \Psi \leftrightarrow F(\Box \Psi)

We will assume the existence of such fixed points for every modal formula with one free variable. This is of course not an obvious thing to assume, but if we interpret \Box as provability in Peano Arithmetic, then the existence of modal fixed points is in fact true.

Modal Rules of Inference

In addition to the existence of modal fixed points, we assume the following rules of inference for the provability operator \Box:

  1. (necessitation) From \vdash A conclude \vdash \Box A: Informally, this says that if A is a theorem, then it is provable.
  2. (internal necessitation) \vdash \Box A \rightarrow \Box \Box A: If A is provable, then it is provable that it is provable.
  3. (box distributivity) \vdash \Box (A \rightarrow B) \rightarrow (\Box A \rightarrow \Box B): This rule allows you to do modus ponens inside the provability operator. If it is provable that A implies B, and A is provable, then B is provable.

Proof of Löb's theorem

  1. Assume that there is a modal sentence P such that \vdash \Box P \rightarrow P.
    Roughly speaking, it is a theorem that if P is provable, then it is, in fact true.
    This is a claim of soundness.
  2. From the existence of modal fixed points for every formula (in particular, the formula X \rightarrow P) it follows there exists a sentence \Psi such that \vdash \Psi \leftrightarrow (\Box \Psi \rightarrow P).
  3. From 2, it follows that \vdash \Psi \rightarrow (\Box \Psi \rightarrow P).
  4. From the necessitation rule, it follows that \vdash \Box(\Psi \rightarrow (\Box \Psi \rightarrow P)).
  5. From 4 and the box distributivity rule, it follows that \vdash \Box\Psi \rightarrow \Box(\Box \Psi \rightarrow P).
  6. Applying the box distributivity rule with  A = \Box \Psi and  B= P gives us \vdash \Box(\Box \Psi \rightarrow P) \rightarrow (\Box\Box\Psi \rightarrow \Box P).
  7. From 5 and 6, it follows that \vdash \Box \Psi \rightarrow (\Box\Box\Psi \rightarrow \Box P).
  8. From the internal necessitation rule, it follows that \vdash \Box \Psi \rightarrow \Box \Box \Psi.
  9. From 7 and 8, it follows that \vdash \Box \Psi \rightarrow \Box P.
  10. From 1 and 9, it follows that \vdash \Box \Psi \rightarrow P.
  11. From 2, it follows that \vdash   (\Box \Psi \rightarrow P) \rightarrow \Psi.
  12. From 10 and 11, it follows that \vdash \Psi
  13. From 12 and the necessitation rule, it follows that \vdash \Box \Psi.
  14. From 13 and 10, it follows that \vdash P.

More on the existence of modal fixed points

Not only does the existence of modal fixed points imply Löb's theorem, but the converse is valid, too. When Löb's theorem is given as an axiom (schema), the existence of a fixed point (up to provable equivalence) p\leftrightarrow A(p) for any formula A(p) modalized in p can be derived.[1] Thus in normal modal logic, Löb's axiom is equivalent to the conjunction of the axiom schema 4, (\Box A\rightarrow \Box\Box A,) and the existence of modal fixed points.

References

  1. Per Lindström (June 2006). "Note on Some Fixed Point Constructions in Provability Logic". Journal of Philosophical Logic 35 (3): 225–230. doi:10.1007/s10992-005-9013-8.

External links

University of Colorado Boulder, Boulder,CO April 13–14, 2013 (Saturday-Sunday) Meeting #1089

This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the Sunday, January 10, 2016. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.