Kemeny–Young method
Part of the Politics series |
Voting systems |
---|
Plurality/Majoritarian |
Other
|
Politics portal |
The Kemeny–Young method is a voting system that uses preferential ballots and pairwise comparison counts to identify the most popular choices in an election. It is a Condorcet method because if there is a Condorcet winner, it will always be ranked as the most popular choice.
This method assigns a score for each possible sequence, where each sequence considers which choice might be most popular, which choice might be second-most popular, which choice might be third-most popular, and so on down to which choice might be least-popular. The sequence that has the highest score is the winning sequence, and the first choice in the winning sequence is the most popular choice. (As explained below, ties can occur at any ranking level.)
The Kemeny–Young method is also known as the Kemeny rule, VoteFair popularity ranking, the maximum likelihood method, and the median relation.
Description
The Kemeny–Young method uses preferential ballots on which voters rank choices according to their order of preference. A voter is allowed to rank more than one choice at the same preference level. Unranked choices are usually interpreted as least-preferred.
Another way to view the ordering is that it is the one which minimizes the sum of the Kendall tau distances (bubble sort distance) to the voters' lists.
Kemeny–Young calculations are usually done in two steps. The first step is to create a matrix or table that counts pairwise voter preferences. The second step is to test all possible rankings, calculate a score for each such ranking, and compare the scores. Each ranking score equals the sum of the pairwise counts that apply to that ranking.
The ranking that has the largest score is identified as the overall ranking. (If more than one ranking has the same largest score, all these possible rankings are tied, and typically the overall ranking involves one or more ties.)
In order to demonstrate how an individual preference order is converted into a tally table, it is worth considering the following example. Suppose that a single voter has a choice among four candidates (i.e. Elliot, Meredith, Roland, and Selden) and has the following preference order:
Preference order |
Choice |
---|---|
First | Elliot |
Second | Roland |
Third | Meredith or Selden (equal preference) |
These preferences can be expressed in a tally table. A tally table, which arranges all the pairwise counts in three columns, is useful for counting (tallying) ballot preferences and calculating ranking scores. The center column tracks when a voter indicates more than one choice at the same preference level. The above preference order can be expressed as the following tally table.
All possible pairs of choice names |
Number of votes with indicated preference | ||
---|---|---|---|
Prefer X over Y | Equal preference | Prefer Y over X | |
X = Selden Y = Meredith |
0 | +1 vote | 0 |
X = Selden Y = Elliot |
0 | 0 | +1 vote |
X = Selden Y = Roland |
0 | 0 | +1 vote |
X = Meredith Y = Elliot |
0 | 0 | +1 vote |
X = Meredith Y = Roland |
0 | 0 | +1 vote |
X = Elliot Y = Roland |
+1 vote | 0 | 0 |
Now suppose that multiple voters had voted on those four candidates. After all ballots have been counted, the same type of tally table can be used to summarize all the preferences of all the voters. Here is an example for a case that has 100 voters.
All possible pairs of choice names |
Number of votes with indicated preference | ||
---|---|---|---|
Prefer X over Y | Equal preference | Prefer Y over X | |
X = Selden Y = Meredith |
50 | 10 | 40 |
X = Selden Y = Elliot |
40 | 0 | 60 |
X = Selden Y = Roland |
40 | 0 | 60 |
X = Meredith Y = Elliot |
40 | 0 | 60 |
X = Meredith Y = Roland |
30 | 0 | 70 |
X = Elliot Y = Roland |
30 | 0 | 70 |
The sum of the counts in each row must equal the total number of votes.
After the tally table has been completed, each possible ranking of choices is examined in turn, and its ranking score is calculated by adding the appropriate number from each row of the tally table. For example, the possible ranking:
- Elliot
- Roland
- Meredith
- Selden
satisfies the preferences Elliot > Roland, Elliot > Meredith, Elliot > Selden, Roland > Meredith, Roland > Selden, and Meredith > Selden. The respective scores, taken from the table, are
- Elliot > Roland: 30
- Elliot > Meredith: 60
- Elliot > Selden: 60
- Roland > Meredith: 70
- Roland > Selden: 60
- Meredith > Selden: 40
giving a total ranking score of 30 + 60 + 60 + 70 + 60 + 40 = 320.
Calculating the overall ranking
After the scores for every possible ranking have been calculated, the ranking that has the largest score can be identified, and becomes the overall ranking. In this case, the overall ranking is:
- Roland
- Elliot
- Selden
- Meredith
with a ranking score of 370.
If there are cycles or ties, more than one possible ranking can have the same largest score. Cycles are resolved by producing a single overall ranking where some of the choices are tied.
Summary matrix
After the overall ranking has been calculated, the pairwise comparison counts can be arranged in a summary matrix, as shown below, in which the choices appear in the winning order from most popular (top and left) to least popular (bottom and right). This matrix layout does not include the equal-preference pairwise counts that appear in the tally table.
... over Roland | ... over Elliot | ... over Selden | ... over Meredith | |
Prefer Roland ... | - | 70 | 60 | 70 |
Prefer Elliot ... | 30 | - | 60 | 60 |
Prefer Selden ... | 40 | 40 | - | 50 |
Prefer Meredith ... | 30 | 40 | 40 | - |
In this summary matrix, the largest ranking score equals the sum of the counts in the upper-right, triangular half of the matrix (shown here in bold, with a green background). No other possible ranking can have a summary matrix that yields a higher sum of numbers in the upper-right, triangular half. (If it did, that would be the overall ranking.)
In this summary matrix, the sum of the numbers in the lower-left, triangular half of the matrix (shown here with a red background) are a minimum. The academic papers by John Kemeny and Peyton Young[2][3] refer to finding this minimum sum, which is called the Kemeny score, and which is based on how many voters oppose (rather than support) each pairwise order.
Method | First-place winner |
---|---|
Kemeny–Young | Roland |
Condorcet | Roland |
Instant runoff voting | Elliot or Selden (depending on how the second-round tie is handled) |
Plurality | Selden |
Example
Imagine that Tennessee is having an election on the location of its capital. The population of Tennessee is concentrated around its four major cities, which are spread throughout the state. For this example, suppose that the entire electorate lives in these four cities and that everyone wants to live as near to the capital as possible.
The candidates for the capital are:
- Memphis, the state's largest city, with 42% of the voters, but located far from the other cities
- Nashville, with 26% of the voters, near the center of the state
- Knoxville, with 17% of the voters
- Chattanooga, with 15% of the voters
The preferences of the voters would be divided like this:
42% of voters (close to Memphis) |
26% of voters (close to Nashville) |
15% of voters (close to Chattanooga) |
17% of voters (close to Knoxville) |
---|---|---|---|
|
|
|
|
This matrix summarizes the corresponding pairwise comparison counts:
... over Memphis |
... over Nashville |
... over Chattanooga |
... over Knoxville | |
Prefer Memphis ... | - | 42% | 42% | 42% |
Prefer Nashville ... | 58% | - | 68% | 68% |
Prefer Chattanooga ... | 58% | 32% | - | 83% |
Prefer Knoxville ... | 58% | 32% | 17% | - |
The Kemeny–Young method arranges the pairwise comparison counts in the following tally table:
All possible pairs of choice names |
Number of votes with indicated preference | ||
---|---|---|---|
Prefer X over Y | Equal preference | Prefer Y over X | |
X = Memphis Y = Nashville |
42% | 0 | 58% |
X = Memphis Y = Chattanooga |
42% | 0 | 58% |
X = Memphis Y = Knoxville |
42% | 0 | 58% |
X = Nashville Y = Chattanooga |
68% | 0 | 32% |
X = Nashville Y = Knoxville |
68% | 0 | 32% |
X = Chattanooga Y = Knoxville |
83% | 0 | 17% |
The ranking score for the possible ranking of Memphis first, Nashville second, Chattanooga third, and Knoxville fourth equals (the unit-less number) 345, which is the sum of the following annotated numbers.
- 42% (of the voters) prefer Memphis over Nashville
- 42% prefer Memphis over Chattanooga
- 42% prefer Memphis over Knoxville
- 68% prefer Nashville over Chattanooga
- 68% prefer Nashville over Knoxville
- 83% prefer Chattanooga over Knoxville
This table lists all the ranking score
.
First choice | Second choice | Third choice | Fourth choice | Ranking score |
---|---|---|---|---|
Memphis | Nashville | Chattanooga | Knoxville | 345 |
Memphis | Nashville | Knoxville | Chattanooga | 279 |
Memphis | Chattanooga | Nashville | Knoxville | 309 |
Memphis | Chattanooga | Knoxville | Nashville | 273 |
Memphis | Knoxville | Nashville | Chattanooga | 243 |
Memphis | Knoxville | Chattanooga | Nashville | 207 |
Nashville | Memphis | Chattanooga | Knoxville | 361 |
Nashville | Memphis | Knoxville | Chattanooga | 295 |
Nashville | Chattanooga | Memphis | Knoxville | 377 |
Nashville | Chattanooga | Knoxville | Memphis | 393 |
Nashville | Knoxville | Memphis | Chattanooga | 311 |
Nashville | Knoxville | Chattanooga | Memphis | 327 |
Chattanooga | Memphis | Nashville | Knoxville | 325 |
Chattanooga | Memphis | Knoxville | Nashville | 289 |
Chattanooga | Nashville | Memphis | Knoxville | 341 |
Chattanooga | Nashville | Knoxville | Memphis | 357 |
Chattanooga | Knoxville | Memphis | Nashville | 305 |
Chattanooga | Knoxville | Nashville | Memphis | 321 |
Knoxville | Memphis | Nashville | Chattanooga | 259 |
Knoxville | Memphis | Chattanooga | Nashville | 223 |
Knoxville | Nashville | Memphis | Chattanooga | 275 |
Knoxville | Nashville | Chattanooga | Memphis | 291 |
Knoxville | Chattanooga | Memphis | Nashville | 239 |
Knoxville | Chattanooga | Nashville | Memphis | 255 |
The largest ranking score is 393, and this score is associated with the following possible ranking, so this ranking is also the overall ranking.
Preference order |
Choice |
---|---|
First | Nashville |
Second | Chattanooga |
Third | Knoxville |
Fourth | Memphis |
If a single winner is needed, the first choice, Nashville, is chosen. (In this example Nashville is the Condorcet winner.)
The summary matrix below arranges the pairwise counts in order from most popular (top and left) to least popular (bottom and right).
... over Nashville ... | ... over Chattanooga ... | ... over Knoxville ... | ... over Memphis ... | |
Prefer Nashville ... | - | 68% | 68% | 58% |
Prefer Chattanooga ... | 32% | - | 83% | 58% |
Prefer Knoxville ... | 32% | 17% | - | 58% |
Prefer Memphis ... | 42% | 42% | 42% | - |
In this arrangement the largest ranking score (393) equals the sum of the counts in bold, which are in the upper-right, triangular half of the matrix (with a green background).
Characteristics
In all cases that do not result in an exact tie, the Kemeny–Young method identifies a most-popular choice, second-most popular choice, and so on.
A tie can occur at any preference level. Except in some cases where circular ambiguities are involved, the Kemeny–Young method only produces a tie at a preference level when the number of voters with one preference exactly matches the number of voters with the opposite preference.
Satisfied criteria for all Condorcet methods
All Condorcet methods, including the Kemeny–Young method, satisfy these criteria:
- Non-imposition
- There are voter preferences that can yield every possible overall order-of-preference result, including ties at any combination of preference levels.
- Condorcet criterion
- If there is a choice that wins all pairwise contests, then this choice wins.
- Majority criterion
- If a majority of voters strictly prefer choice X to every other choice, then choice X is identified as the most popular.
- Non-dictatorship
- A single voter cannot control the outcome in all cases.
Additional satisfied criteria
The Kemeny–Young method also satisfies these criteria:
- Unrestricted domain
- Identifies the overall order of preference for all the choices. The method does this for all possible sets of voter preferences and always produces the same result for the same set of voter preferences.
- Pareto efficiency
- Any pairwise preference expressed by every voter results in the preferred choice being ranked higher than the less-preferred choice.
- Monotonicity
- If voters increase a choice's preference level, the ranking result either does not change or the promoted choice increases in overall popularity.
- Smith criterion
- The most popular choice is a member of the Smith set, which is the smallest nonempty set of choices such that every member of the set is pairwise preferred to every choice not in the Smith set.
- Independence of Smith-dominated alternatives
- If choice X is not in the Smith set, adding or withdrawing choice X does not change a result in which choice Y is identified as most popular.
- Reinforcement
- If all the ballots are divided into separate races and the overall ranking for the separate races are the same, then the same ranking occurs when all the ballots are combined.[4]
- Reversal symmetry
- If the preferences on every ballot are inverted, then the previously most popular choice must not remain the most popular choice.
Failed criteria for all Condorcet methods
In common with all Condorcet methods, the Kemeny–Young method fails these criteria (which means the described criteria do not apply to the Kemeny–Young method):
- Independence of irrelevant alternatives
- Adding or withdrawing choice X does not change a result in which choice Y is identified as most popular.
- Invulnerability to burying
- A voter cannot displace a choice from most popular by giving the choice an insincerely low ranking.
- Invulnerability to compromising
- A voter cannot cause a choice to become the most popular by giving the choice an insincerely high ranking.
- Participation
- Adding ballots that rank choice X over choice Y never cause choice Y, instead of choice X, to become most popular.
- Later-no-harm
- Ranking an additional choice (that was otherwise unranked) cannot displace a choice from being identified as the most popular.
- Consistency
- If all the ballots are divided into separate races and choice X is identified as the most popular in every such race, then choice X is the most popular when all the ballots are combined.
Additional failed criteria
The Kemeny–Young method also fails these criteria (which means the described criteria do not apply to the Kemeny–Young method):
- Independence of clones
- Offering a larger number of similar choices, instead of offering only a single such choice, does not change the probability that one of these choices is identified as most popular.
- Invulnerability to push-over
- A voter cannot cause choice X to become the most popular by giving choice Y an insincerely high ranking.
- Schwartz
- The choice identified as most popular is a member of the Schwartz set.
- Polynomial runtime[5]
- An algorithm is known to determine the winner using this method in a runtime that is polynomial in the number of choices.
Calculation methods
An algorithm for computing the Kemeny-Young ranking in time polynomial in the number of candidates is not known, and unlikely to exist since the problem is NP-hard[5] even if there are just 4 voters.[6]
It has been reported[7] that fast calculation methods based on integer programming sometimes allowed the computation of full rankings for votes on as many as 40 candidates in seconds. However, certain 40-candidate 5-voter Kemeny elections generated using reasonable-sounding random processes were not solvable on a 3 GHz Pentium computer in a useful time bound.
Note that the complexity of computation scales linearly to the number of voters so the time needed to process a given set of votes is dominated by the number of candidates[8] rather than the number of votes, limiting the importance of this constraint to elections where voters are able to effectively consider significantly more than the common seven items of working memory.
There exists a Polynomial-time approximation scheme for computing the ranking,[9] and there exists a parametrized subexponential algorithm with running time O*(2O(√OPT)) for computing ranking.[10]
History
The Kemeny–Young method was developed by John Kemeny in 1959.[2]
In 1978 Peyton Young and Arthur Levenglick showed[3] that this method was the unique neutral method satisfying reinforcement and the Condorcet criterion. In other papers[11] [12] [13] ,[14] Young adopted an epistemic approach to preference-aggregation: he supposed that there was an objectively 'correct', but unknown preference order over the alternatives, and voters receive noisy signals of this true preference order (cf. Condorcet's jury theorem.) Using a simple probabilistic model for these noisy signals, Young showed that the Kemeny–Young method was the maximum likelihood estimator of the true preference order. Young further argues that Condorcet himself was aware of the Kemeny-Young rule and its maximum-likelihood interpretation, but was unable to clearly express his ideas.
In the papers by John Kemeny and Peyton Young, the Kemeny scores use counts of how many voters oppose, rather than support, each pairwise preference,[2][3] but the smallest such score identifies the same overall ranking.
Since 1991 the method has been promoted under the name "VoteFair popularity ranking" by Richard Fobes.[15]
See also
- Comparison of voting systems
Notes
- ↑ The numbers in this example are adapted from .
- 1 2 3 John Kemeny, "Mathematics without numbers", Daedalus 88 (1959), pp. 577–591.
- 1 2 3 H. P. Young and A. Levenglick, "A Consistent Extension of Condorcet's Election Principle", SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics 35, no. 2 (1978), pp. 285–300.
- ↑ Giuseppe Munda, "Social multi-criteria evaluation for a sustainable economy", p. 124.
- 1 2 J. Bartholdi III, C. A. Tovey, and M. A. Trick, "Voting schemes for which it can be difficult to tell who won the election", Social Choice and Welfare, Vol. 6, No. 2 (1989), pp. 157–165.
- ↑ C. Dwork, R. Kumar, M. Naor, D. Sivakumar. Rank Aggregation Methods for the Web, WWW10, 2001
- ↑ Vincent Conitzer, Andrew Davenport, and Jayant Kalagnanam, "Improved bounds for computing Kemeny rankings" (2006).
- ↑
- ↑ "How to Rank with Few Errors". http://cs.brown.edu/~claire/stoc07.pdf
- ↑ Karpinski, M. and Schudy, W., "Faster Algorithms for Feedback Arc Set Tournament, Kemeny Rank Aggregation and Betweenness Tournament", in: Cheong, O., Chwa, K.-Y., and Park, K. (Eds.): ISAAC 2010, Part I, LNCS 6506, pp. 3-14.
- ↑ H. P. Young, "Condorcet's Theory of Voting", American Political Science Review 82, no. 2 (1988), pp. 1231–1244.
- ↑ H. P. Young, "Optimal ranking and choice from pairwise comparisons", in Information pooling and group decision making edited by B. Grofman and G. Owen (1986), JAI Press, pp. 113–122.
- ↑ H. P. Young, "Optimal Voting Rules", Journal of Economic Perspectives 9, no.1 (1995), pp. 51–64.
- ↑ H. P. Young, "Group choice and individual judgements", Chapter 9 of Perspectives on public choice: a handbook, edited by Dennis Mueller (1997) Cambridge UP., pp.181 –200.
- ↑ Richard Fobes, "The Creative Problem Solver's Toolbox", (ISBN 0-9632-2210-4), 1993, pp. 223–225.
External links
- VoteFair.org — A website that calculates Kemeny–Young results. For comparison, it also calculates the winner according to plurality, Condorcet, Borda count, and other voting methods.
- Voting::VoteFairRanking — Open-source software (on the Perl CPAN Archives) that calculates VoteFair ranking results, which include Condorcet-Kemeny calculations.
- Condorcet Class PHP library supporting multiple Condorcet methods, including Kemeny–Young method.
- C++ Program for Kemeny-Young Preference Aggregation — Command-line program for fast calculation of Kemeny-Young results, as source code and compiled binaries for Windows and Linux. Open source, except uses Numerical Recipes.
- Kemeny-Young Optimal Rank Aggregation in Python — tutorial that uses a simple formulation as integer program and is adaptable to other languages with bindings to lpsolve.