Functional completeness
In logic, a functionally complete set of logical connectives or Boolean operators is one which can be used to express all possible truth tables by combining members of the set into a Boolean expression.[1][2] A well-known complete set of connectives is { AND, NOT }, consisting of binary conjunction and negation. The singleton sets { NAND } and { NOR } are also functionally complete.
In a context of propositional logic, functionally complete sets of connectives are also called (expressively) adequate.[3]
From the point of view of digital electronics, functional completeness means that every possible logic gate can be realized as a network of gates of the types prescribed by the set. In particular, all logic gates can be assembled from either only binary NAND gates, or only binary NOR gates.
Formal definition
Given the Boolean domain B = {0,1}, a set F of Boolean functions ƒi: Bni → B is functionally complete if the clone on B generated by the basic functions ƒi contains all functions ƒ: Bn → B, for all strictly positive integers n ≥ 1. In other words, the set is functionally complete if every Boolean function that takes at least one variable can be expressed in terms of the functions ƒi. Since every Boolean function of at least one variable can be expressed in terms of binary Boolean functions, F is functionally complete if and only if every binary Boolean function can be expressed in terms of the functions in F.
A more natural condition would be that the clone generated by F consist of all functions ƒ: Bn → B, for all integers n ≥ 0. However, the examples given above are not functionally complete in this stronger sense because it is not possible to write a nullary function, i.e. a constant expression, in terms of F if F itself does not contain at least one nullary function. With this stronger definition, the smallest functionally complete sets would have 2 elements.
Another natural condition would be that the clone generated by F together with the two nullary constant functions be functionally complete or, equivalently, functionally complete in the strong sense of the previous paragraph. The example of the Boolean function given by S(x, y, z) = z if x = y and S(x, y, z) = x otherwise shows that this condition is strictly weaker than functional completeness.[4][5][6]
Introduction
Modern texts on logic typically take as primitive some subset of the connectives: conjunction (); disjunction (); negation (); material conditional (); and possibly the biconditional (). Further connectives can be defined, if so desired, by defining them in terms of these primitives. For example, NOR (sometimes denoted ) is the conjunction of two negations:
Similarly, NAND can be defined in terms of disjunction and negation. It turns out that every binary connective can be defined in terms of , so this set is functionally complete.
However, this set is not a minimal functionally complete set, because the conditional and biconditional can be defined in terms of the other connectives:
It follows that the smaller set is also functionally complete. But this is still not minimal, as can be defined as
Alternatively, may be defined in terms of in a similar manner, or may be defined in terms of :
No further simplifications are possible. Hence, every two-element set of connectives containing and one of is a minimal functionally complete subsets of .
Characterization of functional completeness
Emil Post proved that a set of logical connectives is functionally complete if and only if it is not a subset of any of the following sets of connectives:
- The monotonic connectives; changing the truth value of any connected variables from F to T without changing any from T to F never makes these connectives change their return value from T to F, e.g. , , , .
- The affine connectives, such that each connected variable either always or never affects the truth value these connectives return, e.g. , , , , .
- The self-dual connectives, which are equal to their own de Morgan dual; if the truth values of all variables are reversed, so is the truth value these connectives return, e.g. , MAJ(p,q,r).
- The truth-preserving connectives; they return the truth value T under any interpretation which assigns T to all variables, e.g. , , , , .
- The falsity-preserving connectives; they return the truth value F under any interpretation which assigns F to all variables, e.g. , , , , .
In fact, Post gave a complete description of the lattice of all clones (sets of operations closed under composition and containing all projections) on the two-element set {T, F}, nowadays called Post's lattice, which implies the above result as a simple corollary: the five mentioned sets of connectives are exactly the maximal clones.
Minimal functionally complete operator sets
When a single logical connective or Boolean operator is functionally complete by itself, it is called a Sheffer function[7] or sometimes a sole sufficient operator. There are no unary operators with this property, and the only binary Sheffer functions — NAND and NOR — are dual. These were discovered but not published by Charles Sanders Peirce around 1880, and rediscovered independently and published by Henry M. Sheffer in 1913.[8] In digital electronics terminology, the binary NAND gate and the binary NOR gate are the only binary universal logic gates.
The following are the minimal functionally complete sets of logical connectives with arity ≤ 2:[9]
- One element
- {NAND}, {NOR}.
- Two elements
- {, ¬}, {, ¬}, {→, ¬}, {←, ¬}, {→, }, {←, }, {→, }, {←, }, {→, }, {→, }, {←, }, {←, }, {, ¬}, {, ¬}, {, }, {, }, {, }, {, }.
- Three elements
- {, , }, {, , }, {, , }, {, , }, {, , }, {, , }.
There are no minimal functionally complete sets of more than three at most binary logical connectives.[9] Constant unary or binary connectives and binary connectives that depend only on one of the arguments have been suppressed to keep the list readable. E.g. the set consisting of binary and the binary connective given by negation of the first argument (ignoring the second) is another minimal functionally complete set.
Examples
- Examples of using the
NAND
completeness. As illustrated by,[10]- ¬A = A
NAND
A - A ∧ B = ¬(A
NAND
B) = (ANAND
B)NAND
(ANAND
B) - A ∨ B = (A
NAND
A)NAND
(BNAND
B)
- ¬A = A
- Examples of using the
NOR
completeness. As illustrated by,[11]- ¬A = A
NOR
A - A ∧ B = (A
NOR
A)NOR
(BNOR
B) - A ∨ B = (A
NOR
B)NOR
(ANOR
B)
- ¬A = A
Note that, an electronic circuit or a software function is optimized by the reuse, that reduce the number of gates. For instance, the "A ∧ B" operation, when expressed by NAND
gates, is implemented with the reuse of "A NAND
B",
- X = (A
NAND
B); A ∧ B = XNAND
X
In other domains
Apart from logical connectives (Boolean operators), functional completeness can be introduced in other domains. For example, a set of reversible gates is called functionally complete, if it can express every reversible operator.
The 3-input Fredkin gate is functionally complete reversible gate by itself – a sole sufficient operator. There are many other three-input universal logic gates, such as the Toffoli gate.
Set theory
There is an isomorphism between the algebra of sets and the Boolean algebra, that is, they have the same structure. Then, if we map boolean operators into set operators, the "translated" above text are valid also for sets: there are many "minimal complete set of set-theory operators" that can generate any other set relations. The more popular "Minimal complete operator sets" are {¬, ∩} and {¬, ∪}.
See also
References
- ↑ Enderton, Herbert (2001), A mathematical introduction to logic (2nd ed.), Boston, MA: Academic Press, ISBN 978-0-12-238452-3. ("Complete set of logical connectives").
- ↑ Nolt, John; Rohatyn, Dennis; Varzi, Achille (1998), Schaum's outline of theory and problems of logic (2nd ed.), New York: McGraw–Hill, ISBN 978-0-07-046649-4. ("[F]unctional completeness of [a] set of logical operators").
- ↑ Smith, Peter (2003), An introduction to formal logic, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0-521-00804-4. (Defines "expressively adequate", shortened to "adequate set of connectives" in a section heading.)
- ↑ Wesselkamper, T.C. (1975), "A sole sufficient operator", Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 16: 86–88, doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1093891614
- ↑ Massey, G.J. (1975), "Concerning an alleged Sheffer function", Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 16 (4): 549–550, doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1093891898
- ↑ Wesselkamper, T.C. (1975), "A Correction To My Paper" A. Sole Sufficient Operator", Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 16 (4): 551, doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1093891899
- ↑ The term was originally restricted to binary operations, but since the end of the 20th century it is used more generally. Martin, N.M. (1989), Systems of logic, Cambridge University Press, p. 54, ISBN 978-0-521-36770-7.
- ↑ Scharle, T.W. (1965), "Axiomatization of propositional calculus with Sheffer functors", Notre Dame J. Formal Logic 6 (3): 209–217, doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1093958259.
- 1 2 Wernick, William (1942) "Complete Sets of Logical Functions," Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 51: 117–32. In his list on the last page of the article, Wernick does not distinguish between ← and →, or between and .
- ↑ "NAND Gate Operations" at http://hyperphysics.phy-astr.gsu.edu/hbase/electronic/nand.html
- ↑ "NOR Gate Operations" at http://hyperphysics.phy-astr.gsu.edu/hbase/electronic/nor.html