Subcategory
In mathematics, a subcategory of a category C is a category S whose objects are objects in C and whose morphisms are morphisms in C with the same identities and composition of morphisms. Intuitively, a subcategory of C is a category obtained from C by "removing" some of its objects and arrows.
Formal definition
Let C be a category. A subcategory S of C is given by
- a subcollection of objects of C, denoted ob(S),
- a subcollection of morphisms of C, denoted hom(S).
such that
- for every X in ob(S), the identity morphism idX is in hom(S),
- for every morphism f : X → Y in hom(S), both the source X and the target Y are in ob(S),
- for every pair of morphisms f and g in hom(S) the composite f o g is in hom(S) whenever it is defined.
These conditions ensure that S is a category in its own right: the collection of objects is ob(S), the collection of morphisms is hom(S), and the identities and composition are as in C. There is an obvious faithful functor I : S → C, called the inclusion functor which takes objects and morphisms to themselves.
Let S be a subcategory of a category C. We say that S is a full subcategory of C if for each pair of objects X and Y of S
A full subcategory is one that includes all morphisms between objects of S. For any collection of objects A in C, there is a unique full subcategory of C whose objects are those in A.
Examples
- The category of finite sets forms a full subcategory of the category of sets.
- The category whose objects are sets and whose morphisms are bijections forms a non-full subcategory of the category of sets.
- The category of abelian groups forms a full subcategory of the category of groups.
- The category of rings with unity (whose morphisms are unit-preserving ring homomorphisms) forms a non-full subcategory of the category of rings.
Embeddings
Given a subcategory S of C the inclusion functor I : S → C is both faithful and injective on objects. It is full if and only if S is a full subcategory.
Some authors define an embedding to be a full and faithful functor. Such a functor is necessarily injective on objects up-to-isomorphism. For instance, the Yoneda embedding is an embedding in this sense.
Some authors define an embedding to be a full and faithful functor that is injective on objects (strictly).[1]
Other authors define a functor to be an embedding if it is faithful and injective on objects. Equivalently, F is an embedding if it is injective on morphisms. A functor F is then called a full embedding if it is a full functor and an embedding.
For any (full) embedding F : B → C the image of F is a (full) subcategory S of C and F induces an isomorphism of categories between B and S. If F is not strictly injective on objects, the image of F is equivalent to B.
In some categories, one can also speak of morphisms of the category being embeddings.
Types of subcategories
A subcategory S of C is said to be isomorphism-closed or replete if every isomorphism k : X → Y in C such that Y is in S also belongs to S. An isomorphism-closed full subcategory is said to be strictly full.
A subcategory of C is wide or lluf (a term first posed by P. Freyd[2]) if it contains all the objects of C. A lluf subcategory is typically not full: the only full lluf subcategory of a category is that category itself.
A Serre subcategory is a non-empty full subcategory S of an abelian category C such that for all short exact sequences
in C, M belongs to S if and only if both and do. This notion arises from Serre's C-theory.
See also
Look up subcategory in Wiktionary, the free dictionary. |
- Reflective subcategory
- Exact category, a full subcategory closed under extensions.
References
- ↑ van Oosten. "Basic category theory" (PDF).
- ↑ Freyd, Peter (1991). "Algebraically complete categories". Proceedings of the International Conference on Category Theory, Como, Italy (CT 1990). Lecture Notes in Mathematics 1488. Springer. pp. 95–104. doi:10.1007/BFb0084215.