Skew lattice

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

In abstract algebra, a skew lattice is an algebraic structure that is a non-commutative generalization of a lattice. While the term skew lattice can be used to refer to any non-commutative generalization of a lattice, over the past twenty years it has been used primarily as follows.

Definition

A skew lattice is a set S equipped with two associative, idempotent binary operations \wedge and \vee , called meet and join, that satisfy the following dual pair of absorption laws

x\wedge (x\vee y)=x=(y\vee x)\wedge x and x\vee (x\wedge y)=x=(y\wedge x)\vee x.

Given that \vee and \wedge are associative and idempotent, these identities are equivalent to the dualities:

x\vee y=x iff x\wedge y=y and x\wedge y=x iff x\vee y=y.[1]

Historical background

For over 60 years, noncommutative variations of lattices have been studied with differing motivations. For some the motivation has been an interest in the conceptual boundaries of lattice theory; for others it was a search for noncommutative forms of logic and Boolean algebra; and for others it has been the behavior of idempotents in rings. A noncommutative lattice, generally speaking, is an algebra (S;\wedge ,\vee ) where \wedge and \vee are associative, idempotent binary operations connected by absorption identities guaranteeing that \wedge in some way dualizes \vee . The precise identities chosen depends upon the underlying motivation, with differing choices producing distinct varieties of algebras. Pascual Jordan, motivated by questions in quantum logic, initiated a study of noncommutative lattices in his 1949 paper, Über Nichtkommutative Verbande,[2] choosing the absorption identities

x\wedge (y\vee x)=x=(x\wedge y)\vee x.

He referred to those algebras satisfying them as Schrägverbände. By varying or augmenting these identities, Jordan and others obtained a number of varieties of noncommutative lattices. Beginning with Jonathan Leech's 1989 paper, Skew lattices in rings,[3] skew lattices as defined above have been the primary objects of study. This was aided by previous results about bands. This was especially the case for many of the basic properties.

Basic properties

Natural partial order and natural quasiorder

In a skew lattice S, the natural partial order is defined by y\leq x if x\wedge y=y=y\wedge x, or dually, x\vee y=x=y\vee x. The natural preorder on S is given by y\preceq x if y\wedge x\wedge y=y or dually x\vee y\vee x=x. While \leq and \preceq agree on lattices, \leq properly refines \preceq in the noncommutative case. The induced natural equivalence D is defined by xDy if x\preceq y\preceq x, that is, x\wedge y\wedge x=x and y\wedge x\wedge y=y or dually, x\vee y\vee x=x and y\vee x\vee y=y. The blocks of the partition S/D are lattice ordered by A>B iff a\in A and b\in B exist such that a>b. This permits us to write Hasse diagrams of skew lattices such as the following pair:

E.g., in the diagram on the left above, that a and b are D related is expressed by the dashed segment. The slanted lines reveal the natural partial order between elements of the distinct D-classes. The elements 1, c and 0 form the singleton D-classes.

Rectangular Skew Lattices

Skew lattices consisting of a single D-class are called rectangular. They are characterized by the equivalent identities: x\wedge y\wedge x=x, y\vee x\vee y=y and x\vee y=y\wedge x. Rectangular skew lattices are isomorphic to skew lattices having the following construction (and conversely): given nonempty sets L and R, on L\times R define (x,y)\vee (z,w)=(z,y) and (x,y)\wedge (z,w)=(x,w). The D-class partition of a skew lattice S , as indicated in the above diagrams, is the unique partition of S into its maximal rectangular subalgebras, Moreover, D is a congruence with the induced quotient algebra S/D being the maximal lattice image of S , thus making every skew lattice S a lattice of rectangular subalgebras. This is the Clifford-McLean Theorem for skew lattices, first given for bands separately by Clifford and McLean. It is also known as the First Decomposition Theorem for skew lattices.

Right (left) handed skew lattices and the Kimura factorization

A skew lattice is right-handed if it satisfies the identity x\wedge y\wedge x=y\wedge x or dually, x\vee y\vee x=x\vee y. These identities essentially assert that x\wedge y=y and x\vee y=x in each D-class. Every skew lattice S has a unique maximal right-handed image S/L where the congruence L is defined by xLy if both x\wedge y=x and y\wedge x=y(or dually, x\vee y=y and y\vee x=x). Likewise a skew lattice is left-handed if x\wedge y=x and x\vee y=y in each D-class. Again the maximal left-handed image of a skew lattice S is the image S/R where the congruence R is defined in dual fashion to L. Many examples of skew lattices are either right or left-handed. In the lattice of congruences, R\vee L=D and R\cap L is the identity congruence \Delta . The induced epimorphism S\rightarrow S/D factors through both induced epimorphisms S\rightarrow S/L and S\rightarrow S/R. Setting T=S/D, the homomorphism k:S\rightarrow S/L\times S/Rdefined by k(x)=(L_{x},R_{x}), induces an isomorphism k*:S\sim S/L\times _{T}S/R. This is the Kimura factorization of S into a fibred product of its maximal right and left-handed images.

Like the Clifford-McLean Theorem, Kimura factorization (or the Second Decomposition Theorem for skew lattices) was first given for regular bands (that satisfy the middle absorption identity, xyxzx=xyzx ). Indeed both \wedge and \vee are regular band operations. The above symbols D, R and L come, of course, from basic semigroup theory.

For more details on the basic properties of a skew lattice please read [3][4][5][6][7][8][9] and.[10]

Subvarieties of skew lattices

Skew lattices form a variety. Rectangular skew lattices, left-handed and right-handed skew lattices all form subvarieties that are central to the basic structure theory of skew lattices. Here are several more.

Symmetric Skew Lattices

A skew lattice S is symmetric if for any x,y\in S , x\wedge y=y\wedge x iff x\vee y=y\vee x. Occurrences of commutation are thus unambiguous for such skew lattices, with subsets of pairwise commuting elements generating commutative subalgebras, i.e, sublattices. ( This is not true for skew lattices in general.) Equational bases for this subvariety, first given by Spinks [11] are: x\vee y\vee (x\wedge y)=(y\wedge x)\vee y\vee x and x\wedge y\wedge (x\vee y)=(y\vee x)\wedge y\wedge x. A lattice section of a skew lattice S is a sublattice T of S meeting each D-class of S at a single element. T is thus an internal copy of the lattice S/D with the composition T\subset S\rightarrow S/D being an isomorphism. All symmetric skew lattices for which |S/D| \leq \aleph_0 , admit a lattice section.[10] Symmetric or not, having a lattice section T guarantees that S also has internal copies of S/L and S/R given respectively by T[R]=\bigcup _{{t\in T}}R_{t} and T[L]=\bigcup _{{t\in T}}L_{t}, where R_{t} and Lt are the R and L congruence classes of t in T . Thus T[R]\subset S\rightarrow S/L and T[L]\subset S\rightarrow S/R are isomorphisms (See [8]). This leads to a commuting diagram of embedding dualizing the preceding Kimura diagram.

Cancellative Skew Lattices

A skew lattice is cancellative if x\vee y=x\vee z and x\wedge y=x\wedge z implies y=z and likewise x\vee z=y\vee z and x\wedge z=y\wedge z implies x=y. Cancellatice skew lattices are symmetric and can be shown to form a variety. Unlike lattices, they need not be distributive, and conversely.

Distributive Skew Lattices

Distributive skew lattices are determined by the identities: x\wedge (y\vee z)\wedge x=(x\wedge y\wedge x)\vee (x\wedge z\wedge x) (D1 ) x\vee (y\wedge z)\vee x=(x\vee y\vee x)\wedge (x\vee z\vee x). (D’1 )

Unlike lattices, (D1 ) and (D‘1 ) are not equivalent in general for skew lattices, but they are for symmetric skew lattices. (See,,.[9][12][13]) The condition (D1 ) can be strengthened to x\wedge (y\vee z)\wedge w=(x\wedge y\wedge w)\vee (x\wedge z\wedge w) (D2 ) in which case (D‘1 ) is a consequence. A skew lattice S satisfies both (D2) and its dual, x\vee (y\wedge z)\vee w=(x\vee y\vee w)\wedge (x\vee z\vee w), if and only if it factors as the product of a distributive lattice and a rectangular skew lattice. In this latter case (D2 ) can be strengthened to x\wedge (y\vee z)=(x\wedge y)\vee (x\wedge z) and (y\vee z)\wedge w=(y\wedge w)\vee (z\wedge w). (D3 ) On its own, (D3 ) is equivalent to (D2 ) when symmetry is added. (See.[3]) We thus have six subvarieties of skew lattices determined respectively by (D1), (D2), (D3) and their duals.

Normal Skew Lattices

As seen above, \wedge and \vee satisfy the identity xyxzx=xyzx. Bands satisfying the stronger identity, xyzx=xzyx, are called normal. A skew lattice is normal skew if it satisfies

x\wedge y\wedge z\wedge x=x\wedge z\wedge y\wedge x.(N)

For each element a in a normal skew lattice S, the set a\wedge S\wedge a defined by { a\wedge x\wedge a|x\in S} or equivalently {x\in S|x\leq a} is a sublattice of S, and conversely. (Thus normal skew lattices have also been called local lattices.) When both \wedge and \vee are normal, S splits isomorphically into a product T\times D of a lattice T and a rectangular skew lattice D, and conversely. Thus both normal skew lattices and split skew lattices form varieties. Returning to distribution, (D2)=(D1)+(N) so that (D2) characterizes the variety of distributive, normal skew lattices, and (D3) characterizes the variety of symmetric, distributive, normal skew lattices.

Categorical Skew Lattices

A skew lattice is categorical if nonempty composites of coset bijections are coset bijections. Categorical skew lattices form a variety. Skew lattices in rings and normal skew lattices are examples of algebras on this variety.[4] Let a>b>c with a\in A, b\in B and c\in C, \varphi be the coset bijection from A to B taking a to b, \psi be the coset bijection from B to C taking b to c and finally \chi be the coset bijection from A to C taking a to c. A skew lattice S is categorical if one always has the equality \psi \circ \varphi =\chi , ie. , if the composite partial bijection \psi \circ \varphi if nonempty is a coset bijection from a C -coset of A to an A-coset of C . That is (A\wedge b\wedge A)\cap (C\vee b\vee C)=(C\vee a\vee C)\wedge b\wedge (C\vee a\vee C)=(A\wedge c\wedge A)\vee b\vee (A\wedge c\wedge A). All distributive skew lattices are categorical. Though symmetric skew lattices might not be. In a sense they reveal the independence between the properties of symmetry and distributivity.

For more details on these and other subvarieties of skew lattices please read [3][6][9][10][11][13][14] and.[4]

Skew Boolean algebras

A zero element in a skew lattice S is an element 0 of S such that for all x\in S, 0\wedge x=0=x\wedge 0 or, dually, 0\vee x=x=x\vee 0. (0)

A Boolean skew lattice is a symmetric, distributive normal skew lattice with 0, (S;\vee ,\wedge ,0), such that a\wedge S\wedge a is a Boolean lattice for each a\in S. Given such skew lattice S , a difference operator \ is defined on [1] by x\ y = x-x\wedge y\wedge x where the latter is evaluated in the Boolean lattice x\wedge S\wedge x. In the presence of (D3) and (0), \ is characterized by the identities: y\wedge x/y=0=x/y\wedge y and (x\wedge y\wedge x)\vee x/y=x=x/y\vee (x\wedge y\wedge x).(SB) One thus has a variety of skew Boolean algebras (S;\vee ,\wedge ,/,0) characterized by identities (D3), (0) and (S B). A primitive skew Boolean algebra consists of 0 and a single non-0 D-class. Thus it is the result of adjoining a 0 to a rectangular skew lattice D via (0) with x/y=x, if y=0 and 0 otherwise. Every skew Boolean algebra is a subdirect product of primitive algebras. Skew Boolean algebras play an important role in the study of discriminator varieties and other generalizations in universal algebra of Boolean behavior. For more details on skew Boolean algebras see [15] [16] [17] [18] [19] [20] [21] [22] [23] [24] .[25]

Skew lattices in rings

Let A be a Ring and let E(A) denote the set of all Idempotents in A. For all x,y\in A set x\wedge y=xy and x\vee y=x+y-xy.

Clearly \wedge but also \vee is associative. If a subset S\subseteq E(A) is closed under \wedge and \vee , then (S,\wedge ,\vee ) is a distributive, cancellative skew lattice. To find such skew lattices in E(A) one looks at bands in E(A), especially the ones that are maximal with respect to some constraint. In fact, every multiplicative band in () that is maximal with respect to being right regular (= ) is also closed under \vee and so forms a right-handed skew lattice. In general, every right regular band in E(A) generates a right-handed skew lattice in E(A). Dual remarks also hold for left regular bands (bands satisfying the identity xyx=xy) in E(A). Maximal regular bands need not to be closed under \vee as defined; counterexamples are easily found using multiplicative rectangular bands. These cases are closed, however, under the cubic variant of \vee defined by x\nabla y=x+y+yx-xyx-yxy since in these cases x\nabla y reduces to yx to give the dual rectangular band. By replacing the condition of regularity by normality (xyzw=xzyw), every maximal normal multiplicative band S in E(A) is also closed under \nabla with (S;\wedge ,\vee ,/,0), where x/y=x-xyx, forms a Boolean skew lattice. When E(A) itself is closed under multiplication, then it is a normal band and thus forms a Boolean skew lattice. In fact, any skew Boolean algebra can be embedded into such an algebra. (See.[26]) When A has a multiplicative identity 1, the condition that E(A) is multiplicatively closed is well-known to imply that E(A) forms a Boolean algebra. Skew lattices in rings continue to be a good source of examples and motivation. For more details read.[23][27][28][29][30]

Primitive skew lattices

Skew lattices consisting of exactly two D-classes are called primitive skew lattices. Given such a skew lattice S with D-classes A>B in S/D, then for any a\in A and b\in B, the subsets

A\wedge b\wedge A={u\wedge b\wedge u:u\in A} \subseteq B and B\vee a\vee B= {v\vee a\vee v:v\in B} \subseteq A

are called, respectively, cosets of A in B and cosets of B in A. These cosets partition B and A with binA\wedge b\wedge A and a\in B\wedge a\wedge B. Cosets are always rectangular subalgebras in their D-classes. What is more, the partial order \geq induces a coset bijection \varphi :B\vee a\vee B\rightarrow A\wedge b\wedge A defined by:

\phi (x)=y iff x>y, for x\in B\vee a\vee B and y\in A\wedge b\wedge A.

Collectively, coset bijections describe \geq between the subsets A and B. They also determine \vee and \wedge for pairs of elements from distinct D-classes. Indeed, given a\in A and b\in B, let \varphi be the cost bijection between the cosets B\vee a\vee B in A and A\wedge b\wedge A in B. Then:

a\vee b=a\vee \varphi -1(b),b\vee a=\varphi -1(b)\vee a and a\wedge b=\varphi (a)\wedge b,b\wedge a=b\wedge \varphi (a).

In general, given a,c\in A and b,d\in B with a>b and c>d, then a,c belong to a common B- coset in A and b,d belong to a common A-coset in B if and only if a>b//c>d. Thus each coset bijection is, in some sense, a maximal collection of mutually parallel pairs a>b.

Every primitive skew lattice S factors as the fibred product of its maximal left and right- handed primitive images S/R\times _{2}S/L. Right-handed primitive skew lattices are constructed as follows. Let A=\cup _{i}A_{i} and B=\cup _{j}B_{j} be partitions of disjoint nonempty sets A and B, where all A_{i} and B_{j} share a common size. For each pair i,j pick a fixed bijection \varphi _{i},j from A_{i} onto B_{j}. On A and B separately set x\wedge y=y and x\vee y=x; but given a\in A and b\in B, set

a\vee b=a,b\vee a=a',a\wedge b=b and b\wedge a=b'

where \varphi _{{i,j}}(a')=b and \varphi _{{i,j}}(a)=b' with a' belonging to the cell A_{i} of a and b' belonging to the cell B_{j} of b. The various \varphi i,j are the coset bijections. This is illustrated in the following partial Hasse diagram where |A_{i}|=|B_{j}|=2 and the arrows indicate the \varphi _{{i,j}} -outputs and \geq from A and B.

One constructs left-handed primitive skew lattices in dual fashion. All right [left] handed primitive skew lattices can be constructed in this fashion. (See [3] Section 1.)

The coset structure of skew lattices

A nonrectangular skew lattice S is covered by its maximal primitive skew lattices: given comparable D-classes A>B in S/D, A\cup B forms a maximal primitive subalgebra of S and every D-class in S lies in such a subalgebra. The coset structures on these primitive subalgebras combine to determine the outcomes x\vee y and x\wedge y at least when x and y are comparable under \preceq . It turns out that x\vee y and x\wedge y are determined in general by cosets and their bijections, although in a slightly less direct manner than the \preceq -comparable case. In particular, given two incomparable D-classes A and B with join D-class J and meet D-class M in S/D, interesting connections arise between the two coset decompositions of J (or M) with respect to A and B. (See [4] Section 3.)

Thus a skew lattice may be viewed as a coset atlas of rectangular skew lattices placed on the vertices of a lattice and coset bijections between them, the latter seen as partial isomorphisms between the rectangular algebras with each coset bijection determining a corresponding pair of cosets. This perspective gives, in essence, the Hasse diagram of the skew lattice, which is easily drawn in cases of relatively small order. (See the diagrams in Section 3 above.) Given a chain of D-classes A>B>C in S/D, one has three sets of coset bijections: from A to B, from B to C and from A to C. In general, given coset bijections \varphi :A\rightarrow B and \psi :B\rightarrow C, the composition of partial bijections \psi \varphi could be empty. If it is not, then a unique coset bijection \chi :A\rightarrow C exists such that \psi \varphi \subseteq \chi . (Again, \chi is a bijection between a pair of cosets in A and C.) This inclusion can be strict. It is always an equality (given \psi \varphi \neq \emptyset ) on a given skew lattice S precisely when S is categorical. In this case, by including the identity maps on each rectangular D-class and adjoining empty bijections between properly comparable D-classes, one has a category of rectangular algebras and coset bijections between them. The simple examples in Section 3 are categorical.

See also

References

  1. 1.0 1.1 Leech, J, Skew lattices in rings, Algebra Universalis, 26(1989), 48-72.
  2. Jordan, P. Uber Nichtkommutative Verbände, Arch. Math. 2 (1949), 56–59.
  3. 3.0 3.1 3.2 3.3 3.4 Leech, J, Skew lattices in rings, Algebra Universalis, 26(1989), 48-72
  4. 4.0 4.1 4.2 4.3 Leech, J, Recent developments in the theory of skew lattices, Semigroup Forum, 52(1996), 7-24.
  5. Leech, J, Magic squares, finite planes and simple quasilattices, Ars Combinatoria 77(2005), 75-96.
  6. 6.0 6.1 Leech, J, The geometry of skew lattices, Semigroup Forum, 52(1993), 7-24.
  7. Leech, J, Normal skew lattices, Semigroup Forum, 44(1992), 1-8.
  8. 8.0 8.1 Cvetko-Vah, K, Internal decompositions of skew lattices, Communications in Algebra, 35 (2007), 243-247
  9. 9.0 9.1 9.2 Cvetko-Vah, K, A new proof of Spinks’ Theorem, Semigroup Forum 73 (2006), 267-272.
  10. 10.0 10.1 10.2 Laslo, G and Leech, J, Green’s relations on noncommutative lattices, Acta Sci. Math. (Szeged), 68 (2002), 501-533.
  11. 11.0 11.1 Spinks, M, Automated deduction in non-commutative lattice theory, Tech. Report 3/98, Monash U, GSCIT, 1998
  12. Spinks, M, Automated deduction in non-commutative lattice theory, Tech. Report 3/98, Monash University, Gippsland School of Computing and Information Technology, June 1998
  13. 13.0 13.1 Spinks, M, On middle distributivity for skew lattices, Semigroup Forum 61 (2000). 341-345.
  14. Cvetko-Vah, Karin ; Kinyon, M. ; Leech, J. ; Spinks, M. Skew Lattices with cancel lation. Pre-Print. Journal of Algebra and Its Applications, 2008
  15. Bignall, R. J., Quasiprimal Varieties and Components of Universal Algebras, Dissertation, The Flinders University of South Australia, 1976.
  16. Bignall, R J, A non-commutative multiple-valued logic, Proc. 21st International Symposium on Multiple-valued Logic, 1991, IEEE Computer Soc. Press, 49-54.
  17. Bignall, R J and J Leech, Skew Boolean algebras and discriminator varieties, Algebra Universalis, 33(1995), 387-398.
  18. Bignall, R J and M Spinks, Propositional skew Boolean logic, Proc. 26th International Symposium on Multiple-valued Logic, 1996, IEEE Computer Soc. Press, 43-48.
  19. Bignall, R J and M Spinks, Implicative BCS-algebra subreducts of skew Boolean algebras, Scientiae Mathematicae Japonicae, 58 (2003), 629-638.
  20. Bignall, R J and M Spinks, On binary discriminator varieties (I): Implicative BCS-algebras, International Journal of Algebra and Computation, to appear.
  21. Cornish, W H, Boolean skew algebras, Acta Math. Acad. Sci. Hung., 36 (1980), 281-291.
  22. Leech, J, Skew Boolean algebras, Algebra Universalis, 27(1990), 497-506.
  23. 23.0 23.1 Leech and Spinks, Skew Boolean algebras generated from generalized Boolean algebras, Algebra Universalis 58 (2008), 287-302.
  24. Spinks, M, Contributions to the Theory of Pre-BCK Algebras, Monash University Dissertation, 2002.
  25. Spinks, M and R Veroff, Axiomatizing the skew Boolean propositional calculus, J.Automated Reasoning, 37 (2006), 3-20.
  26. Cvetko-Vah, K, Skew lattices in matrix rings, Algebra Universalis 53 (2005), 471-479.
  27. Cvetko-Vah, K, Pure skew lattices in rings, Semigroup Forum 68 (2004), 268-279.
  28. Cvetko-Vah, K, Pure ∇-bands, Semigroup Forum 71 (2005), 93-101.
  29. Cvetko-Vah, K, Skew lattices in rings, Dissertation, University of Ljubljana, 2005.
  30. Cvetko-Vah, K and J Leech, Associativity of the ∇-operation on bands in rings, Semigroup Forum 76 (2008), 32-50
This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike; additional terms may apply for the media files.