Natural number
In mathematics, the natural numbers are those used for counting ("there are six coins on the table") and ordering ("this is the third largest city in the country"). These purposes are related to the linguistic notions of cardinal and ordinal numbers, respectively (see English numerals). A later notion is that of a nominal number, which is used only for naming.
Properties of the natural numbers related to divisibility, such as the distribution of prime numbers, are studied in number theory. Problems concerning counting and ordering, such as partition enumeration, are studied in combinatorics.
There is no universal agreement about whether to include zero in the set of natural numbers: some define the natural numbers to be the positive integers {1, 2, 3, ...}, while for others the term designates the non-negative integers {0, 1, 2, 3, ...}. The former definition is the traditional one, with the latter definition having first appeared in the 19th century.
History of natural numbers and the status of zero
The most primitive method of representing a natural number is to put down a dot for each object. Later, a set of objects could be tested for equality, excess or shortage, by striking out a dot for each object in the set.
The first major advance in abstraction was the use of numerals to represent numbers. This allowed systems to be developed for recording large numbers. The ancient Egyptians developed a powerful system of numerals with distinct hieroglyphs for 1, 10, and all the powers of 10 up to over 1 million. A stone carving from Karnak, dating from around 1500 BC and now at the Louvre in Paris, depicts 276 as 2 hundreds, 7 tens, and 6 ones; and similarly for the number 4,622. The Babylonians had a place-value system based essentially on the numerals for 1 and 10.[citation needed]
A much later advance was the development of the idea that 0 can be considered as a number, with its own numeral. The use of a 0 digit in place-value notation (within other numbers) dates back as early as 700 BC by the Babylonians, but they omitted such a digit when it would have been the last symbol in the number.[1] The Olmec and Maya civilizations used 0 as a separate number as early as the 1st century BC, but this usage did not spread beyond Mesoamerica.[citation needed] The use of a numeral 0 in modern times originated with the Indian mathematician Brahmagupta in 628. However, 0 had been used as a number in the medieval computus (the calculation of the date of Easter), beginning with Dionysius Exiguus in 525, without being denoted by a numeral (standard Roman numerals do not have a symbol for 0); instead nulla or nullae, genitive of nullus, the Latin word for "none", was employed to denote a 0 value.[2]
The first systematic study of numbers as abstractions (that is, as abstract entities) is usually credited to the Greek philosophers Pythagoras and Archimedes. Many Greek mathematicians did not consider 1 to be "a number", so to them 2 was the smallest number.[3]
Independent studies also occurred at around the same time in India, China, and Mesoamerica.[citation needed]
Several set-theoretical definitions of natural numbers were developed in the 19th century. With these definitions it was convenient to include 0 (corresponding to the empty set) as a natural number. Including 0 is now the common convention among set theorists, logicians, and computer scientists. Many other mathematicians also include 0, although some have kept the older tradition and take 1 to be the first natural number.[4] The term counting number is also used to refer to the natural numbers (either including or excluding 0). Likewise, some authors use the term whole number to mean a natural number including 0; some use it to mean a natural number excluding 0; while others use it in a way that includes both 0 and the negative integers, as an equivalent of the term integer.[5]
In using indices, beginning with 1 is still common (there is no 0-th row or column of a matrix), except when (as is often the case) the beginning is a rather trivial form of the problem fittingly numbered zero (the first and second Fibonacci number are 1 whatever form of is used, yet it is convenient, and often done, to begin with a 0th Fibonacci number, which is 0). In all areas of mathematics that deal with spaces of some sort, as a rule includes zero, because (e.g.) is the logical (even if in itself trivial) beginning of a series of spaces of ascending dimension.
Notation
Mathematicians use N or (an N in blackboard bold, displayed as ℕ in Unicode) to refer to the set of all natural numbers. This set is countably infinite: it is infinite but countable by definition. This is also expressed by saying that the cardinal number of the set is aleph-null .[6]
To be unambiguous about whether 0 is included or not, sometimes an index (or superscript) "0" is added in the former case, and a superscript "" or subscript "" is added in the latter case:[citation needed]
Some authors who exclude 0 from the naturals may distinguish the set of nonnegative integers by referring to the latter as the natural numbers with zero, whole numbers, or counting numbers, denoted W.[citation needed] Others use the notation P for the positive integers if there is no danger of confusing this with the prime numbers.[citation needed] In that case, a popular[citation needed] notation is to use a script P for positive integers (which extends to using script N for negative integers, and script Z for 0).
Set theorists often denote the set of all natural numbers including 0 by a lower-case Greek letter omega: ω. This stems from the identification of an ordinal number with the set of ordinals that are smaller. Moreover, adopting the von Neumann definition of ordinals and defining cardinal numbers as minimal ordinals among those with same cardinality leads to the identity .
Algebraic properties
The addition (+) and multiplication (×) operations on natural numbers have several algebraic properties:
- Closure under addition and multiplication: for all natural numbers a and b, both a + b and a × b are natural numbers.
- Associativity: for all natural numbers a, b, and c, a + (b + c) = (a + b) + c and a × (b × c) = (a × b) × c.
- Commutativity: for all natural numbers a and b, a + b = b + a and a × b = b × a.
- Existence of identity elements: for every natural number a, a + 0 = a and a × 1 = a.
- Distributivity of multiplication over addition for all natural numbers a, b, and c, a × (b + c) = (a × b) + (a × c).
- No nonzero zero divisors: if a and b are natural numbers such that a × b = 0, then a = 0 or b = 0.
Properties
One can recursively define an addition on the natural numbers by setting a + 0 = a and a + S(b) = S(a + b) for all a, b. Here S should be read as "successor". This turns the natural numbers (N, +) into a commutative monoid with identity element 0, the so-called free object with one generator. This monoid satisfies the cancellation property and can be embedded in a group (in the mathematical sense of the word group). The smallest group containing the natural numbers is the integers.
If 1 is defined as S(0), then b + 1 = b + S(0) = S(b + 0) = S(b). That is, b + 1 is simply the successor of b.
Analogously, given that addition has been defined, a multiplication × can be defined via a × 0 = 0 and a × S(b) = (a × b) + a. This turns (N*, ×) into a free commutative monoid with identity element 1; a generator set for this monoid is the set of prime numbers. Addition and multiplication are compatible, which is expressed in the distribution law: a × (b + c) = (a × b) + (a × c). These properties of addition and multiplication make the natural numbers an instance of a commutative semiring. Semirings are an algebraic generalization of the natural numbers where multiplication is not necessarily commutative. The lack of additive inverses, which is equivalent to the fact that N is not closed under subtraction, means that N is not a ring; instead it is a semiring (also known as a rig).
If the natural numbers are taken as "excluding 0", and "starting at 1", the definitions of + and × are as above, except that they begin with a + 1 = S(a) and a × 1 = a.
For the remainder of the article, juxtaposed variables such as ab indicate the product a × b, and the standard order of operations is assumed.
A total order on the natural numbers is defined by letting a ≤ b if and only if there exists another natural number c with a + c = b. This order is compatible with the arithmetical operations in the following sense: if a, b and c are natural numbers and a ≤ b, then a + c ≤ b + c and ac ≤ bc. An important property of the natural numbers is that they are well-ordered: every non-empty set of natural numbers has a least element. The rank among well-ordered sets is expressed by an ordinal number; for the natural numbers this is expressed as ω.
While it is in general not possible to divide one natural number by another and get a natural number as result, the procedure of division with remainder is available as a substitute: for any two natural numbers a and b with b ≠ 0 there are natural numbers q and r such that
- a = bq + r and r < b.
The number q is called the quotient and r is called the remainder of division of a by b. The numbers q and r are uniquely determined by a and b. This Euclidean division is key to several other properties (divisibility), algorithms (such as the Euclidean algorithm), and ideas in number theory.
Generalizations
Two generalizations of natural numbers arise from the two uses:
- A natural number can be used to express the size of a finite set; more generally a cardinal number is a measure for the size of a set also suitable for infinite sets; this refers to a concept of "size" such that if there is a bijection between two sets they have the same size. The set of natural numbers itself and any other countably infinite set has cardinality aleph-null ().
- Linguistic ordinal numbers "first", "second", "third" can be assigned to the elements of a totally ordered finite set, and also to the elements of well-ordered countably infinite sets like the set of natural numbers itself. This can be generalized to ordinal numbers which describe the position of an element in a well-ordered set in general. An ordinal number is also used to describe the "size" of a well-ordered set, in a sense different from cardinality: if there is an order isomorphism between two well-ordered sets they have the same ordinal number. The first ordinal number that is not a natural number is expressed as ; this is also the ordinal number of the set of natural numbers itself.
Many well-ordered sets with cardinal number have an ordinal number greater than (the latter is the lowest possible). The least ordinal of cardinality (i.e., the initial ordinal) is .
For finite well-ordered sets, there is one-to-one correspondence between ordinal and cardinal numbers; therefore they can both be expressed by the same natural number, the number of elements of the set. This number can also be used to describe the position of an element in a larger finite, or an infinite, sequence.
Hypernatural numbers are part of a non-standard model of arithmetic due to Skolem.
Other generalizations are discussed in the article on numbers.
Formal definitions
Historically, the precise mathematical definition of the natural numbers developed with some difficulty. The Peano axioms state conditions that any successful definition must satisfy. Certain constructions show that, given set theory, models of the Peano postulates must exist.
Peano axioms
The Peano axioms give a formal theory of the natural numbers. The axioms are:
- There is a natural number 0.
- Every natural number a has a natural number successor, denoted by S(a). Intuitively, S(a) is a + 1.
- There is no natural number whose successor is 0.
- S is injective, i.e. distinct natural numbers have distinct successors: if a ≠ b, then S(a) ≠ S(b).
- If a property is possessed by 0 and also by the successor of every natural number which possesses it, then it is possessed by all natural numbers. (This postulate ensures that the proof technique of mathematical induction is valid.)
It should be noted that the "0" in the above definition need not correspond to the number zero. "0" simply means some object that when combined with an appropriate successor function, satisfies the Peano axioms. All systems that satisfy these axioms are elementarily equivalent in first-order logic, however, there exists models for the Peano axioms which are uncountable; these are called non-standard models for arithmetic and are guaranteed by the Upward Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem. The name "0" is used here for the first element (the term "zeroth element" has been suggested to leave "first element" to "1", "second element" to "2", etc.), which is the only element that is not a successor. For example, the natural numbers starting with 1 also satisfy the axioms, if the symbol 0 is interpreted as the natural number 1, the symbol S(0) as the number 2, etc. In fact, in Peano's original formulation, the first natural number was 1.
Constructions based on set theory
A standard construction
A standard construction in set theory, a special case of the von Neumann ordinal construction,[7] is to define the natural numbers as follows:
- Set 0 := { }, the empty set,
- and define S(a) = a ∪ {a} for every set a. S(a) is the successor of a, and S is called the successor function.
- By the axiom of infinity, the set of all natural numbers exists and is the intersection of all sets containing 0 which are closed under this successor function. This then satisfies the Peano axioms.
- Each natural number is then equal to the set of all natural numbers less than it, so that
- 0 = { }
- 1 = {0} = {{ }}
- 2 = {0, 1} = {0, {0}} = {{ }, }
:*3 = {0, 1, 2} = {0, {0}, {0, {0}}} ={{ }, {{ }}, {{ }, }}
- n = {0, 1, 2, ..., n−2, n−1} = {0, 1, 2, ..., n−2,} ∪ {n−1} = {n−1} ∪ (n−1) = S(n−1)
- and so on.
When a natural number is used as a set, this is typically what is meant. Under this definition, there are exactly n elements (in the naïve sense) in the set n, and n ≤ m (in the naïve sense) if and only if n is a subset of m.
Also, with this definition, different possible interpretations of notations like Rn (n-tuples versus mappings of n into R) coincide.
Even if one does not accept the axiom of infinity and therefore cannot accept that the set of all natural numbers exists, it is still possible to define what it means to be one of these sets. For a set n to be a natural number means that it is either 0 (empty) or a successor, and each of its elements is either 0 or the successor of another of its elements.
Other constructions
Although the standard construction is useful, it is not the only possible construction. For example:
- one could define 0 = { }
- and S(a) = {a},
- producing
- 0 = { }
- 1 = {0} ={{ }}
- 2 = {1} = {{{}}}, etc.
- Each natural number is then equal to the set of the natural number preceding it.
It is also possible to define 0 = {{ }}
- and S(a) = a ∪ {a}
- producing
- 0 = {{ }}
- 1 = {{ }, 0} = {{ }, {{ }}}
- 2 = {{ }, 0, 1}, etc.
The oldest and most "classical" set-theoretic definition of the natural numbers is the definition commonly ascribed to Frege and Russell under which each concrete natural number n is defined as the set of all sets with n elements.[8][9] This may appear circular, but can be made rigorous with care. Define 0 as {{ }} (clearly the set of all sets with zero elements) and define S(A) (for any set A) as {x ∪ {y} | x ∈ A ∧ y ∉ x} (see set-builder notation). Then 0 will be the set of all sets with zero elements, 1 = S(0) will be the set of all sets with one element, 2 = S(1) will be the set of all sets with two elements, and so forth. The set of all natural numbers can be defined as the intersection of all sets containing 0 as an element and closed under S (that is, if the set contains an element n, it also contains S(n)). One could also define "finite" independently of the notion of "natural number", and then define natural numbers as equivalence classes of finite sets under the equivalence relation of equipollence. This definition does not work in the usual systems of axiomatic set theory because the collections involved are too large (it will not work in any set theory with the axiom of separation); but it does work in New Foundations (and in related systems known to be relatively consistent) and in some systems of type theory.
See also
- Canonical representation of a positive integer
- Countable set
- Integer
Notes
- ↑ "A history of Zero". MacTutor History of Mathematics. Retrieved 2013-01-23. "... a tablet found at Kish ... thought to date from around 700 BC, uses three hooks to denote an empty place in the positional notation. Other tablets dated from around the same time use a single hook for an empty place"
- ↑ Michael L. Gorodetsky (2003-08-25). "Cyclus Decemnovennalis Dionysii – Nineteen year cycle of Dionysius". Hbar.phys.msu.ru. Retrieved 2012-02-13.
- ↑ This convention is used, for example, in Euclid's Elements, see Book VII, definitions 1 and 2.
- ↑ This is common in texts about Real analysis. See, for example, Carothers (2000) p.3 or Thomson, Bruckner and Bruckner (2000), p.2.
- ↑ Weisstein, Eric W., "Counting Number" and "Whole Number", MathWorld.
- ↑ Weisstein, Eric W., "Cardinal Number", MathWorld.
- ↑ Von Neumann 1923
- ↑ Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik: eine logisch-mathematische Untersuchung über den Begriff der Zahl (1884). Breslau.
- ↑ Whitehead, Alfred North, and Bertrand Russell. Principia Mathematica, 3 vols, Cambridge University Press, 1910, 1912, and 1913. Second edition, 1925 (Vol. 1), 1927 (Vols 2, 3). Abridged as Principia Mathematica to *56, Cambridge University Press, 1962.
References
- Landau, Edmund (1966). Foundations of Analysis (3 ed.). Chelsea Pub Co. ISBN 0-8218-2693-X.
- Dedekind, Richard (1963). Essays on the Theory of Numbers. Dover. ISBN 0-486-21010-3.
- Dedekind, Richard (2007). Essays on the Theory of Numbers. Kessinger Publishing, LLC. ISBN 0-548-08985-X.
- N.L. Carothers, Real analysis, Cambridge University Press, 2000, ISBN 0-521-49756-6.
- Brian S. Thomson, Judith B. Bruckner, Andrew M. Bruckner. Elementary Real Analysis, ClassicalRealAnalysis.com, 2000, ISBN 0-13-019075-6.
- Von Neumann, Johann (1923), "Zur Einführung der trasfiniten Zahlen", Acta litterarum ac scientiarum Ragiae Universitatis Hungaricae Francisco-Josephinae, Sectio scientiarum mathematicarum 1: 199–208
- Von Neumann, John (January 2002) [1923], "On the introduction of transfinite numbers", in Jean van Heijenoort, From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931 (3rd ed.), Harvard University Press, pp. 346–354, ISBN 0-674-32449-8 - English translation of von Neumann 1923.
External links
- Hazewinkel, Michiel, ed. (2001), "Natural number", Encyclopedia of Mathematics, Springer, ISBN 978-1-55608-010-4
- Axioms and Construction of Natural Numbers
- Essays on the Theory of Numbers by Richard Dedekind at Project Gutenberg
- Weisstein, Eric W., "Natural Number", MathWorld.
|