Lazy argument

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

The lazy argument (ἀργὸς λόγος) is an attempt at undermining the philosophical doctrine of fatalism.

Argument

The argument posits that any action to change circumstances in life is futile as life has already been fated; for example, when we feel sick, why should we call the doctor or do anything at all to help change the circumstances we find ourselves in if the outcome is ultimately fated? We will either recover or die and, according to the doctrine of fatalism, one of these options has already been 'chosen' or fated for us, so what is the point in taking any action to change the condition in which we are living if the end result has been predetermined? It can be subsequently concluded that we ought to do nothing, because regardless of the way we act in the aforementioned situation, fate has ultimately predetermined the results and thus our actions are futile.

Refutation

The Stoic philosopher Chrysippus' refutation of the lazy argument is given in Cicero's 'On Fate' ('De fato'). The argument, presented by Cicero, calls upon the idea that an event is 'co-fated' with other events. As in the example above, if it is fated for someone to recover from an illness, then the necessary steps towards recovery are also fated, and can be said to be co-fated along with this final event; so whilst recovery will occur, the steps towards recovery must also occur and evidently will occur if one is truly fated to recover.

The lazy argument only seems plausible if one fails to consider the necessity of the occurrence of intermediate events related to a final, fated event. Yet this is unsound and thus the lazy argument must be rejected. Consider this hypothetical argument; if at a given time it is fated that I will pass an exam, the lazy argument would suggest that it is as equally as justifiable for me to not study as it would be to study, because I will pass the exam regardless of any action I may take. This is due to the fact that, after all, it is fated for me to pass the exam, however, whilst my passing of the exam is in fact fated, it is also dependent on my completion of a series of events beforehand and thus, if I do not complete these intermediate events, then ultimately, I will not pass my test. All human actions – in fact, our destiny – are decided by our relation to things, or as Chrysippus put it, events are "co-fated" to occur:

The non-destruction of one's coat, he says, is not fated simply, but co-fated with its being taken care of, and someone's being saved from his enemies is co-fated with his fleeing those enemies; and having children is co-fated with being willing to lie with a woman. ... For many things cannot occur without our being willing and indeed contributing a most strenuous eagerness and zeal for these things, since, he says, it was fated for these things to occur in conjunction with this personal effort. ... But it will be in our power, he says, with what is in our power being included in fate.[1]

Notes

  1. Diogenianus in Eusebius, Praeparatio evangelica, vi. 8, quoted in Inwood & Gerson 1997, p. 190

Sources

This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike; additional terms may apply for the media files.