John Niemeyer Findlay
John Niemeyer Findlay | |
---|---|
Born |
25 November 1903 Pretoria, Orange River Colony |
Died | 27 September 1987 |
Nationality | South African |
Alma mater | University of Graz |
Spouse(s) | Aileen Hawthorn |
John Niemeyer Findlay, known as J. N. Findlay (25 November 1903 – 27 September 1987), was a South African philosopher.
Education and career
After reading classics and philosophy as a boy and at the University of Pretoria, Findlay received a Rhodes scholarship to Balliol College Oxford for the years 1924–1926 before completing his doctorate in 1933 at Graz, where he studied under Ernst Mally. From 1926 to 1966 he was professor of philosophy at the University of Pretoria, the University of Otago in New Zealand, Rhodes University College, Grahamstown, the University of Natal, Pietermartizburg, King’s College, Newcastle upon Tyne, and King's College London. Following retirement from his chair at London (1966) and a year at the University of Texas at Austin, Findlay continued to teach full-time for more than twenty years, first as Clark Professor of Moral Philosophy and Metaphysics at Yale University (1967–1972), then as University Professor and Borden Parker Bowne Professor of Philosophy (succeeding Peter Bertocci) at Boston University (1972–1987).[1][2][3] He was president of the Aristotelian Society from 1955 to 1956 and president of the Metaphysical Society of America from 1974 to 1975, as well as a Fellow of both the British Academy and the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. He was also an Editorial Advisor of the journal Dionysius. A chair for visiting professors at Boston University carries his name, as does a biennial award given for the best book in metaphysics, as judged by the Metaphysical Society of America. Findlay betrayed a great commitment to the welfare and formation[4] of generations of students (Leroy S. Rouner was fond of introducing him as "Plotinus incarnate"), teaching philosophy in one college classroom after another for sixty-two consecutive academic years. On 10 September 2012 Findlay was voted the 8th "most underappreciated philosopher active in the U.S. from roughly 1900 through mid-century" in a poll conducted among readers of Leiter Reports: A Philosophy Blog, finishing behind George Santayana, Alfred North Whitehead, and Clarence Irving Lewis.
Rational Mysticism
At a time when scientific materialism, positivism, linguistic analysis, and ordinary language philosophy were the core academic ideas, Findlay championed phenomenology, revived Hegelianism, and wrote works that were inspired by Theosophy,[5] Buddhism, Plotinus, and Idealism. In his books published in the 1960s, including two series of Gifford Lectures, Findlay developed Rational Mysticism. According to this mystical system, "the philosophical perplexities, e.g., concerning universals and particulars, mind and body, knowledge and its objects, the knowledge of other minds,"[6] as well as those of free will and determinism, causality and teleology, morality and justice, and the existence of temporal objects, are human experiences of deep antinomies and absurdities about the world. Findlay's conclusion is that these necessitate the postulation of higher spheres, or "latitudes", where objects' individuality, categorical distinctiveness and material constraints are diminishing, lesser in each latitude than in the one below it. On the highest spheres, existence is evaluative and meaningful more than anything else, and Findlay identifies it with the idea of The Absolute.[7] In 2012 Findlay's major work on Plato along with both volumes of his "cave lectures" returned into print courtesy of the Routledge Revivals series .
Husserl
Findlay translated into English Husserl's Logische Untersuchungen (Logical Investigations), which he regarded as the author's best work, representing a developmental stage when the idea of phenomenological bracketing was not yet taken as the basis of a philosophical system, covering in fact for loose subjectivism. To Findlay, the work was also one of the peaks of philosophy generally, suggesting superior alternatives both for overly minimalistic or naturalistic efforts in ontology and for Ordinary Language treatments of consciousness and thought.[8][9] Findlay also contributed final editing and wrote addenda to translations of Hegel's Logic and Phenomenology of Spirit. In 2013 Oxford University Press added Findlay's Kant book to the list of works it now reprints on demand .
Ludwig Wittgenstein
Findlay was first a follower, and then an outspoken critic, of Ludwig Wittgenstein. He denounced his three theories of meaning, arguing against the idea of Use, prominent in Wittgenstein's later period and in his followers, that it is insufficient for an analysis of meaning without such notions as connotation and denotation, implication, syntax and most originally, pre-existent meanings, in the mind or the external world, that determine linguistic ones, such as Husserl has evoked. Findlay credits Wittgenstein with great formal, aesthetic and literary appeal, and of directing well-deserved attention to Semantics and its difficulties.[10]
References
- ↑ Howard, Alana. "Biography". Gifford Lecture Series. Retrieved 2008-07-10.
- ↑ Harris, Errol (Spring 1988), "In Memoriam: John Niemeyer Findlay", Owl of Minerva 19 (2): 252–253
- ↑ "Awards • Department of Philosophy at Boston University". Retrieved 2008-07-10.
- ↑ '"I owe to [Findlay’s] teaching, directly or indirectly, all that I know of either Logic or Ethics" (A. N. Prior).
- ↑ "[My Gifford Lectures] ... represent my attempt to cull an eternal, necessary theosophy from the defective theosophic teaching of my adolescence" (Studies in the Philosophy of J. N. Findlay, p. 45). Findlay's Gifford Lectures also may well constitute the most comprehensive defense of the doctrine of the transmigration of the soul (reincarnation) in 20th-century academic philosophy.
- ↑ Findlay, J. N. (1966), "Preface", written at London, The Transcendence of the Cave, New York: Humanities Press (published 1967)
- ↑ Drob, Sanford L, Findlay's Rational Mysticism: An Introduction
- ↑ Findlay, J. N. (1970), "Translator's Introduction (Abridged)", written at New Haven, Connecticut, in Moran, Dermot, Logical Investigations I, New York: Routledge (published 2001), ISBN 0-415-24189-8
- ↑ Ryle, Gilbert; Findlay, J. N. (1961), "Symposium: Use, Usage and Meaning", Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 35: 240, retrieved 2008-06-14
- ↑ Ryle, Gilbert; Findlay, J. N. (1961), "Symposium: Use, Usage and Meaning", Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 35: 231–242, retrieved 2008-06-14
Works
Books
- Meinong's Theory of Objects, Oxford University Press, 1933; 2nd ed. as Meinong's Theory of Objects and Values, 1963
- Hegel: A Re-examination, London: Allen & Unwin/New York: Macmillan, 1958
- Values and Intentions, London: Allen & Unwin, 1961
- Language, Mind and Value, London: Allen & Unwin/New York: Humanities Press, 1963
- The Discipline of the Cave, London: Allen & Unwin/New York: Humanities Press, 1966 (Gifford Lectures 1964–1965 )
- The Transcendence of the Cave, London: Allen & Unwin/New York: Humanities Press, 1967 (Gifford Lectures 1965–1966 )
- Axiological Ethics, London: Macmillan, 1970
- Ascent to the Absolute, London: Allen & Unwin/New York: Humanities Press, 1970
- Psyche and Cerebrum, Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1972
- Plato: The Written and Unwritten Doctrines, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul/New York: Humanities Press, 1974
- Plato and Platonism, New York: New York Times Book Co., 1976
- Kant and the Transcendental Object, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981
- Wittgenstein: A Critique, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1984
Articles
- "Time: A Treatment of Some Puzzles", Australasian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy, Vol. 19, Issue 13 (December 1941): 216–235.
- "Morality by Conventions", Mind, Vol. 33, No. 210 (1944): 142–169
- "Can God's Existence Be Disproved?", Mind, Vol. 37, No. 226 (1948): 176–183; reprinted with discussion in Flew, A. and MacIntyre, A. C., (eds.), New Essays in Philosophical Theology, New York: Macmillan, 1955
- "Linguistic Approach to Psychophysics", Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 1949–1950
- "The Justification of Attitudes", Mind, Vol. 43, No. 250 (1954): 145–161
- "Use, Usage and Meaning", Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, Vol. 35. (1961), pp. 223–242
- "Foreword", in Hegel's Logic, Being Part One of The Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1830), Clarendon Press, 1975. ISBN 978-0-19-824512-4
- "Foreword", in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit, Oxford University Press, 1977. ISBN 0-19-824597-1
- "Analysis of the Text", in Phenomenology of Spirit, Oxford University Press, 1977: 495–592. ISBN 978-0-19-824597-1
- "The Myths of Plato", Dionysius, Volume II (1978): 19–34
Bibliography
- Robert S. Cohen, Richard M. Martin, and Merold Westphal (eds.), Studies in the Philosophy of J.N. Findlay, Albany NY: State University of New York Press, 1985 (Includes autobiographical note by Findlay and his account of encounters with Wittgenstein). ISBN 978-0-87395-795-3
- Michele Marchetto, L'etica impersonale: La teoria dei valori di John Niemeyer Findlay, Edizioni scientifiche italiane, 1989. ISBN 978-88-7104-138-4; Eng. tr. 1989, Impersonal Ethics: John Niemeyer Findlay's Value-theory, Avebury, 1996. ISBN 978-1-85972-272-5
- Bockja Kim, Morality as the End of Philosophy: The Teleological Dialectic of the Good in J.N. Findlay's Philosophy of Religion, University Press of America, 1999. ISBN 978-0-7618-1490-0
External links
- John Niemeyer Findlay by Dr. Sanford L. Drob
- Philosophical History: The Otago Department
- Gifford Lecture Series – Biography – John Niemeyer Findlay
|