Evolutionary epistemology
Part of a series on |
Evolutionary biology |
---|
Natural history |
History of evolutionary theory |
Fields and applications
|
Social implications |
|
Evolutionary epistemology refers to three distinct topics: (1) the biological evolution of cognitive mechanisms in animals and humans, (2) a theory that knowledge itself evolves by natural selection, and (3) the study of the historical discovery of new abstract entities such as abstract number or abstract value that necessarily precede the individual acquisition and usage of such abstractions.
A theory about cognition in biological evolution
"Evolutionary epistemology" can refer to a branch of epistemology that applies the concepts of biological evolution to the growth of animal and human cognition. It argues that the mind is in part genetically determined and that its structure and function reflect adaptation, a nonteleological process of interaction between the organism and its environment. A cognitive trait tending to increase inclusive fitness in a given population should therefore grow more common over time, and a trait tending to prevent its carriers from passing on their genes should show up less and less frequently.
A theory about the growth of knowledge
"Evolutionary epistemology" can also refer to a theory that applies the concepts of biological evolution to the growth of human knowledge, and argues that units of knowledge themselves, particularly scientific theories, evolve according to selection. In this case, a theory—like the germ theory of disease—becomes more or less credible according to changes in the body of knowledge surrounding it.
One of the hallmarks of evolutionary epistemology is the notion that empirical testing does not justify the truth of scientific theories, but rather that social and methodological processes select those theories with the closest "fit" to a given problem. The mere fact that a theory has survived the most rigorous empirical tests available does not, in the calculus of probability, predict its ability to survive future testing. Karl Popper used Newtonian physics as an example of a body of theories so thoroughly confirmed by testing as to be considered unassailable, but which were nevertheless overturned by Einstein's bold insights into the nature of space-time. For the evolutionary epistemologist, all theories are true only provisionally, regardless of the degree of empirical testing they have survived.
A theory about the process of discovering new abstract entities
"Evolutionary epistemology" can also refer to the opposite of (onto)genetic epistemology, namely phylogenetic epistemology as the historical discovery and reification of abstractions that necessarily precedes the learning of such abstractions by individuals. Piaget dismissed this possibility, stating 'The fundamental hypothesis of genetic epistemology is that there is a parallelism between the progress made in the logical and rational organization of knowledge and the corresponding formative psychological processes. Well, now, if that is our hypothesis, what will be our field of study? Of course the most fruitful, most obvious field of study would be reconstituting human history: the history of human thinking in prehistoric man. Unfortunately, we are not very well informed about the psychology of Neanderthal man or about the psychology of Homo siniensis of Teilhard de Chardin. Since this field of biogenesis is not available to us, we shall do as biologists do and turn to ontogenesis. Nothing could be more accessible to study than the ontogenesis of these notions. There are children all around us.' (Piaget 1974) Piaget was mistaken in so quickly dismissing the study of phylogenetic epistemology, as there is much historical data available about the origins and evolution of the various notational systems that reify different kinds of abstract entity.
Popper is considered by many to have given evolutionary epistemology its first comprehensive treatment, though Donald T. Campbell coined the phrase in 1974 (Schilpp, 1974), and Piaget alluded to it in 1974 (Piaget, 1974, p. 13).
See also
- Genetic epistemology
- Memetics
- Evolutionary psychology
- Gerhard Vollmer
- Konrad Lorenz, Behind the Mirror: A Search for a Natural History of Human Knowledge
- Rupert Riedl
- Karl Popper
- Donald T. Campbell
- Multiple discovery
- Universal Darwinism
- Jean Piaget
References
- Karl R. Popper. Objective Knowledge, An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford University Press, 1972.
- Schilpp, P. A., ed. The Philosophy of Karl R. Popper. LaSalle, IL. Open Court. 1974. See Campbell's essay, "Evolutionary Epistemology" on pp. 412–463.
- Stephen Toulmin, Human Understanding: Volume 1: The Collective Use and Evolution of Concepts, 1972.
- Riedl, R. Biology of Knowledge: The Evolutionary Basis of Reason, Chichester: John Wiley & Sons, 1984.
- Harms, William F., Information and Meaning in Evolutionary Processes (Cambridge Studies in Philosophy and Biology) , 2004
- Piaget, J. Genetic Epistemology. 1974
External links
- Evolutionary Epistemology entry by Michael Bradie and William Harms in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2008-01-04
- Evolutionary epistemology at PhilPapers
- Evolutionary epistemology at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
- Evolutionary epistemology entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy by N. Gontier.
- Links on Evolutionary Theory and Memetics from Principia Cybernetica Web
- Selection Theory Bibliography by Gary A. Cziko and Donald T. Campbell