In set theory, the cardinality of the continuum is the cardinality or “size” of the set of real numbers , sometimes called the continuum. It is an infinite cardinal number and is denoted by or (a lowercase fraktur script c).
The real numbers are more numerous than the natural numbers . Moreover, has the same number of elements as the power set of . Symbolically, if the cardinality of is denoted as , the cardinality of the continuum is
This was proven by Georg Cantor in his 1874 uncountability proof, part of his groundbreaking study of different infinities, and later more simply in his diagonal argument. Cantor defined cardinality in terms of bijective functions: two sets have the same cardinality if and only if there exists a bijective function between them.
Between any two real numbers a < b, no matter how close they are to each other, there are always infinitely many other real numbers, and Cantor showed that they are as many as those contained in the whole set of real numbers. In other words, the open interval (a,b) is equinumerous with This is also true for several other infinite sets, such as any n-dimensional Euclidean space (see Space filling curve). That is,
The smallest infinite cardinal number is (aleph-naught). The second smallest is (aleph-one). The continuum hypothesis, which asserts that there are no sets whose cardinality is strictly between and implies that .
Contents |
Georg Cantor introduced the concept of cardinality to compare the sizes of infinite sets. He famously showed that the set of real numbers is uncountably infinite; i.e. is strictly greater than the cardinality of the natural numbers, :
In other words, there are strictly more real numbers than there are integers. Cantor proved this statement in several different ways. See Cantor's first uncountability proof and Cantor's diagonal argument.
A variation on Cantor's diagonal argument can be used to prove Cantor's theorem which states that the cardinality of any set is strictly less than that of its power set, i.e. |A| < 2|A|, and so the power set P(N) of the natural numbers N is uncountable. In fact, it can be shown that the cardinality of P(N) is equal to :
By the Cantor–Bernstein–Schroeder theorem we conclude that
(A different proof of is given in Cantor's diagonal argument. This proof constructs a bijection from {0,1}N to R.)
The cardinal equality can be demonstrated using cardinal arithmetic:
This argument is a condensed version of the notion of interleaving two binary sequences: let 0.a0a1a2... be the binary expansion of x and let 0.b0b1b2... be the binary expansion of y. Then z = 0.a0b0a1b1a2b2..., the interleaving of the binary expansions, is a well-defined function when x and y have unique binary expansions. Only countably many reals have non-unique binary expansions.
By using the rules of cardinal arithmetic one can also show that
where n is any finite cardinal ≥ 2, and
where is the cardinality of the power set of R, and .
Every real number has an infinite decimal expansion. For example,
(This is true even when the expansion repeats as in the first two examples.) In any given case, the number of digits is countable since they can be put into a one-to-one correspondence with the set of natural numbers . This fact makes it sensible to talk about (for example) the first, the one-hundredth, or the millionth digit of . Since the natural numbers have cardinality each real number has digits in its expansion.
Since each real number can be broken into an integer part and a decimal fraction, we get
since
On the other hand, if we map to and consider that decimal fractions containing only 3 or 7 are only a part of the real numbers, then we get
and thus
The sequence of beth numbers is defined by setting and . So is the second beth number, beth-one:
The third beth number, beth-two, is the cardinality of the power set of R (i.e. the set of all subsets of the real line):
The famous continuum hypothesis asserts that is also the second aleph number . In other words, the continuum hypothesis states that there is no set whose cardinality lies strictly between and
This statement is now known to be independent of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC). That is, both the hypothesis and its negation are consistent with these axioms. In fact, for every nonzero natural number n, the equality = is independent of ZFC. (The case is the continuum hypothesis.) The same is true for most other alephs, although in some cases equality can be ruled out by König's theorem on the grounds of cofinality, e.g., In particular, could be either or , where is the first uncountable ordinal, so it could be either a successor cardinal or a limit cardinal, and either a regular cardinal or a singular cardinal.
A great many sets studied in mathematics have cardinality equal to . Some common examples are the following:
Sets with cardinality greater than include:
They all have cardinality (Beth two).
This article incorporates material from cardinality of the continuum on PlanetMath, which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share-Alike License.