Xenophanes

Xenophanes of Colophon (Ancient Greek: Ξενοφάνης ὁ Κολοφώνιος IPA: [ksenopʰánɛːs ho kolopʰɔ̌ːnios], English: /zəˈnɒfənz/; c.570 – c.475 BC)[1] was a Greek philosopher, theologian, poet, and social and religious critic. Xenophanes life was one of travel, having left Ionia at the age of 25 he continued to travel throughout the Greek world for another 67 years.[2] Some scholars say he lived in exile in Siciliy.[3] Knowledge of his views comes from fragments of his poetry, surviving as quotations by later Greek writers. To judge from these, his elegiac and iambic[4] poetry criticized and satirized a wide range of ideas, including Homer and Hesiod, the belief in the pantheon of anthropomorphic gods and the Greeks' veneration of athleticism. He is the earliest Greek poet who claims explicitly to be writing for future generations, creating "fame that will reach all of Greece, and never die while the Greek kind of songs survives."[5]

Contents

Theology

Xenophanes' surviving writings display a skepticism that became more commonly expressed during the fourth century. He satirized traditional religious views of his time as human projections, and for this he is often regarded as the "Feuerbach of Antiquity," which did the same for Christianity.[6] He aimed his critique at the polytheistic religious views of earlier Greek poets and of his own contemporaries: "Homer and Hesiod" one fragment states, "have attributed to the gods all sorts of things that are matters of reproach and censure among men: theft, adultery, and mutual deception." Sextus Empiricus reported that[7] such observations were appreciated by Christian apologists. Xenophanes is quoted, memorably, in Clement of Alexandria,[8] arguing against the conception of gods as fundamentally anthropomorphic:

But if cattle and horses and lions had hands
or could paint with their hands and create works such as men do,
horses like horses and cattle like cattle
also would depict the gods' shapes and make their bodies
of such a sort as the form they themselves have.
...
Ethiopians say that their gods are snub–nosed [σιμούς] and black
Thracians that they are pale and red-haired.[9]

Other passages quoted by Clement of Alexandria that argue against the traditional Greek conception of gods include:

  1. "One god, greatest among gods and humans,
    like mortals neither in form nor in thought."[10]
  2. Two "But mortals think that the gods are born
    and have the mortals' own clothes and voice and form"[11]

Regarding Xenophanes' theology five key concepts about God can be formed. God is: beyond human morality, does not resemble human form, cannot die or be born (God is divine thus eternal), no divine hierarchy exists, and God does not intervene in human affairs.[12] While Xenophanes is rejecting Homeric theology, he is not questioning the presence of a divine entity, rather his philosophy is a critique on Ancient Greek writers and their conception of divinity[13] There is also the concept of God being whole with the universe, essentially controlling it, while at the same time being physically unconnected.[14] It would seem, however, that this notion of God being intertwined with the universe contradicts Xenophanes' physical philosophy.

Xenophanes espoused a belief that "God is one, supreme among gods and men, and not like mortals in body or in mind."[15] He maintained there was one greatest God. God is one eternal being, spherical in form, comprehending all things within himself, is intelligent, and moves all things, but bears no resemblance to human nature either in body or mind. He is considered by some to be a precursor to Parmenides and Spinoza. Because of his development of the concept of a "one god greatest among gods and men" that is abstract, universal, unchanging, immobile and always present, Xenophanes is often seen as one of the first monotheists, in the Western philosophy of religion, though this vision is disputed.

Physical Ideas

Xenophanes wrote about two extremes predominating the world: wet and dry (water and earth).[16] These two extreme states would alternate between one another and with the alteration human life would become extinct then regenerate (or vise versa depending on the dominant form).[17] The idea of alternating states and human life perishing and coming back suggests he believed in the principle of causation; another distinguishing step that Xenophanes takes from Ancient philosophical traditions to ones based more on scientific observation.[18] The argument can be considered a rebuke to Anaixmenes' air theory.[19] A detailed account of the wet and dry form theory is found in Hippolytus' Refutation.

Xenophanes concluded from his examination of fossils that water once must have covered all of the Earth's surface. The use of evidence is an important step in advancing from simply stating an idea to backing it up by evidence and observation.[20]

Knowing

Xenophanes is credited with being one of the first philosophers to distinguish between true belief and knowledge, which he further developed into the prospect that you can know something but not really know it.[21] If the statement seems unclear, that's because it is. Due to the lack of whole works by Xenophanes a lot of meaning is lost and a whole lot of guessing is at hand, so that the implication of knowing being something deeper ("a clearer truth") may have special implications or it just may mean that you can't know something just by looking at it.[22] It is known that the most and widest variety of evidence was considered by Xenophanes to be the surest way to prove a theory.[23]

His epistemology, which is still influential today, held that there actually exists a truth of reality, but that humans as mortals are unable to know it. Karl Popper read Xenophanes as saying that it is possible to act only on the basis of working hypotheses—we may act as if we knew the truth, as long as we know that this is extremely unlikely.[24] Xenophanes' views then might serve as a basis of Critical rationalism.

In today's philosophical and classics discourse, Xenophanes is seen as one of the most important presocratic philosophers. It had also been common since antiquity to see him as the teacher of Zeno of Elea, the colleague of Parmenides, and generally associated with the Eleatic school, but common opinion today is likewise that this is false (see Lesher, p. 102).

There is one fragment dealing with the management of a feast, another which denounces the exaggerated importance attached to athletic victories, and several which deny the humanized gods of Homer. Arguments such as these made Xenophanes infamous for his attacks on "conventional military and athletic virtues of the time" and well known to side with the intellectual instead.[25]

Notes

  1. ^ Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  2. ^ Charles H. Khan "Xenophanes" Who's Who in the Classical World. Ed. Simon Hornblower and Tony Spawforth. Oxford University Press, 2000. Oxford Reference Online. Oxford University Press. 12 October 2011.
  3. ^ "Xenophanes of Colophon" The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Simon Blackburn. Oxford University Press, 2008. Oxford Reference Online. Oxford University Press. 12 October 2011.
  4. ^ Early Greek philosophy By Jonathan Barnes Page 40 ISBN 0140444610
  5. ^ See Dalby, Andrew (2006), Rediscovering Homer, New York, London: Norton, ISBN 0393057887  p. 123.
  6. ^ Johansen, Karsten Friis A history of ancient philosophy: from the beginnings to Augustine p.49
  7. ^ Sextus Empiricus, Against the Mathematicians, I.289, and IX.192f.
  8. ^ Clement, Miscellanies V.110 and VII.22.
  9. ^ Diels-Kranz, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, Xenophanes frr. 15-16. Many other translations of this passage have Xenophanes state that the Thracians were "blond".
  10. ^ Osborne, Catherine. "Chapter 4." Presocratic Philosopohy: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford UP. 62. Print.
  11. ^ Osborne, Catherine. "Chapter 4." Presocratic Philosopohy: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford UP. 62. Print.
  12. ^ McKirahan, Richard D. "Xenophanes of Colophon. Philosophy Before Socrates. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1994. 60-62. Print.
  13. ^ McKirahan, Richard D. "Xenophanes of Colophon. Philosophy Before Socrates. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1994. 61. Print.
  14. ^ McKirahan, Richard D. "Xenophanes of Colophon. Philosophy Before Socrates. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1994. 60-62. Print.
  15. ^ Zeller, Vorsokrastische Philosophie, p. 530, n. 3.
  16. ^ McKirahan, Richard D. "Xenophanes of Colophon. Philosophy Before Socrates. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1994. 65. Print.
  17. ^ McKirahan, Richard D. "Xenophanes of Colophon. Philosophy Before Socrates. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1994. 66. Print.
  18. ^ McKirahan, Richard D. "Xenophanes of Colophon. Philosophy Before Socrates. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1994. 66. Print.
  19. ^ McKirahan, Richard D. "Xenophanes of Colophon. Philosophy Before Socrates. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1994. 65. Print.
  20. ^ McKirahan, Richard D. "Xenophanes of Colophon. Philosophy Before Socrates. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1994. 66. Print.
  21. ^ Osborne, Catherine. "Chapter 4." Presocratic Philosopohy: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford UP. 66-67. Print.
  22. ^ Osborne, Catherine. "Chapter 4." Presocratic Philosopohy: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford UP. 67. Print.
  23. ^ McKirahan, Richard D. "Xenophanes of Colophon. Philosophy Before Socrates. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1994. 66. Print.
  24. ^ K. Popper, A. Friemuth Petersen, J. Mejer: The World of Parmenides, p. 46
  25. ^ "Xenophanes of Colophon" The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Simon Blackburn. Oxford University Press, 2008. Oxford Reference Online. Oxford University Press. 12 October 2011.

Bibliography

Editions

Further reading

External links