Schema (Kant)

In Kantian philosophy, a schema (plural: schemata) is the procedural rule by which a category or pure, non-empirical concept is associated with a mental image of an object. It is supposedly produced by the imagination in relation to time.

Contents

Role in Kant's architectonic system

Kant created an architectonic system in which there is a progression of phases from the most formal to the most empirical.[1] "Kant develops his system of corporeal nature in the following way. He starts in the Critique with the most formal act of human cognition, called by him the transcendental unity of apperception, and its various aspects, called the logical functions of judgment. He then proceeds to the pure categories of the understanding, and then to the schematized categories, and finally to the transcendental principles of nature in general."[2] It is within this system that the transcendental schemata are supposed to serve a crucial purpose.

Purpose of the Schematism chapter

Kant wrote the chapter on Schematism in his Critique of Pure Reason to solve the problem of "...how we can ensure that categories have 'sense and significance.' "[3]

A posteriori concepts have sense when they are derived from a mental image that is based on experienced sense impressions. Kant's a priori concepts, on the other hand, are alleged to have sense when they are derived from a non–experienced mental schema, trace, outline, sketch, monogram,[4] or minimal image. This is similar to a Euclidean geometrical diagram.

Whenever two things are totally different from each other, yet must interact, there must be some common characteristic that they share in order to somehow relate to one another. Categories, or a priori concepts, have, according to Kant, a basic and necessary importance for human knowledge, even though they are totally different from sensations. However, they must be connected in some way with sensed experience[5] because "… an a priori concept which cannot, as it were, establish any empirical connections is a fraud … the purpose of the Schematism chapter was to show that the categories at least do have satisfactory empirical connections."[6]

Explication of the Kantian account of schemata

Three types of concepts and their schemata

There are three types of concept that require a schema in order to connect them to perceptions so that they have sense [Sinn] and meaning [Bedeutung]. These three types are (1) empirical concepts, (2) pure sensuous concepts, and (3) pure concepts of the understanding, or Categories. The first two employ schemata. The third employs transcendental schemata.

Empirical concepts

An empirical concept is the abstract thought of that which is common to several perceptions. When an empirical concept is said to contain an object, whatever is thought in the concept must be intuited in the mental representation of the object.[7] Examples of intuitive perceptions that are the content of empirical concepts are vague images that are imagined in order to connect a concept with the perceptions from which it was derived as their common feature.[8] "Intuitions," Kant wrote, "are always required to verify or demonstrate the reality of our concepts."[9] These examples ensure that "our abstract thinking has not strayed far from the safe ground of perception, and has possibly become somewhat high–flown or even a mere idle display of words.".[10] This is because "concepts are quite impossible, and are utterly without meaning or signification, unless an object is given for the concepts themselves, or at least for the elements of which they consist."[11] For example, "The concept of a dog signifies a rule according to which my imagination can trace, delineate, or draw a general outline, figure, or shape of a four-footed animal without being restricted to any single and particular shape supplied by experience."[12] In order to prevent the emptiness of "thoughts without contents",[13] it is "necessary to make our concepts sensible, i.e., to add an object of intuition to them."[13] In order to test whether a concept is sensible, we sometimes " … go back to perception only tentatively and for the moment, by calling up in imagination a perception corresponding to the concept that occupies us at the moment, a perception that can never be quite adequate to the (general) concept, but is a mere representative of it for the time being. … Kant calls a fleeting phantasm of this kind a schema."[14]

Pure sensuous concepts

These are concepts that relate, prior to experience, to the external sense of space and the internal sense of time. As such, they are mathematical in that they refer to geometry and arithmetic. A pure, sensuous concept is the construction or mental drawing of what is common to several geometrical figures. These mathematical concepts are not based on objective visual images. They are based on schemata that exist only in thought. Any particular image could not be as general as the concept.[12] The schemata are rules that allow the imagination to mentally construct or draw or trace a pure, general geometrical form that gives the pure, sensuous concept significance. "… [T]o possess the schema corresponding to the concept triangle is to be able to envisage the variety of things to which the word "triangle" applies."[15] "[T]he schema of sensuous concepts (such as of figures in space) is a product and, as it were, a monogram of the pure imagination a priori. Images become possible only through the schema. But the images must always be connected with the concept only by means of the designated schema. Otherwise, the images can never be fully congruent to the general concept."[16]

Pure concepts of the understanding

A pure concept of the understanding, or category, is a characteristic, predicate, attribute, quality, or property of any possible object, that is, an object in general or as such. These concepts are not abstractions of what is common to several perceived, particular, individual objects, as are empirical concepts. "Since the categories are a priori and are therefore not abstractions from sense perceptions, they owe their origin to the very nature of the mind itself."[17] They are not derived from perceptions of external objects, as are empirical concepts. Instead, they are the result of the way that the mind is constituted or formed. They come from within, not without.

Kant claimed that the schemata of pure, non-empirical concepts, or categories, provide a reference to intuition in a way similar to the manner of empirical concepts. "If the concepts are empirical, the intuitions are called examples: if they are pure concepts of the understanding, the intuitions are called schemata."[9] In the same way that examples provide signification for empirical concepts, schemata help to answer the question of "whether operating with the categories is anything other than playing with words."[18]

Since the pure concepts of the understanding, or categories, are characteristics of all objects in general, they can never be associated with the image of any specific, particular, individual object. "Since they are pure, they cannot be pictures..."[19] "Yet there must be some connection between the abstract idea and the experienced world to which the idea is expected to apply..."[20] "In order for the pure categories to have objective validity (and not merely subjective validity) they must be related to sensibility."[21]

Applying pure concepts to sense impressions

The categories, or pure concepts of the understanding,[22] are a priori logical innate forms that are conditions of the possibility of things in general, or of things as such.[23] A thing can become a known object of thought when an a posteriori sense impression is comprehended through the forms of the categories. Categories and sense impressions are totally different from each other. Categories are utterly heterogeneous with the perceptions that are experienced through the sense organs. In order for specific phenomena of Nature to be thought from the combination of categories (pure concepts) and sense perceptions, there must be a third, mediating procedure that connects them. This mediator is a transcendental schema.[24] Transcendental schemata meaningfully join the empty "thoughts without content" and the blind "intuitions without concepts."[25]

Schemata that mediate between empirical (a posteriori) concepts or mathematical (pure sensuous) concepts and perceptions are similar to adapters. Just as adapters are devices for fitting together incompatible parts, schemata connect empirical concepts with the perceptions from which they were derived. Schemata are rules for the production of images. As rules, they are related to concepts. As image–producers, they are related to perceptions. "While the concept belongs to the understanding and its instance to perception, the schema has, so to speak, a foot in either domain. As rules for the production of images the schemata … are linked to the understanding; as rules for the production of images they are linked to perception."[26] The "adapter" simile is even more apt in the case of transcendental schemata. This is because pure concepts of the understanding (Categories) are totally unrelated to perceptions. The pure concepts or Categories are original constituent components of the understanding and are not derived from empirical sense perceptions.

Transcendental Schemata

Transcendental schema are not related to empirical concepts or to mathematical concepts. These schemata connect pure concepts of the understanding, or categories, to the phenomenal appearance of objects in general, that is, objects as such, or all objects.[27]

Judgment

Transcendental Schematism results from the ability to make judgments. Judgment applies "the concepts of the understanding [the Categories] to phenomena." [28] " … [T]he judgment … schematizes these concepts a priori and applies these schemata, without which no experiential judgment would be possible, to each empirical synthesis. … the transcendental schematism of judgment provides it [judgment] with a rule under which given empirical intuitions are to be subsumed."[29] Kant defined the Greek word hypotyposis as a " … rendering perceptible to the senses, making sensual (Versinnlichung)."[9] The usual definition is "example, pattern, outline, or sketch." If a hypotyposis is schematic, according to Kant, "...to a concept, which is comprehended by the understanding, the corresponding intuition is given a priori..."[9] This is in opposition to a symbolic hypotyposis, like God, in which the concept can only be thought by Reason and to which no sensible intuition can be adequate. Schemata contain direct presentations of the concept. They make this presentation demonstratively, not by the use of analogies. Judgment, according to Kant, works mechanically with given appearances and brings them under concepts. It does this as a tool that is utilized and controlled by both the understanding and the senses.[30]

Time

The schematism of the pure understanding is "the sensuous condition [time] under which alone pure concepts of the understanding [the Categories] can be used."[31] Categories, or pure concepts of the understanding, are abstract representations of objects in general. However, they can result in thought about particular, specific internal or external objects if they are related to time. All concepts are derived from perceptions, therefore pure concepts [Categories] are based on pure perceptions. The purest perception, or schema, is time. Time has the purest relation to sensation that is possible. It is the mere form of sensation because sensations must be felt in succession. Therefore, time was designated by Kant as the purest possible schema of a pure concept.

Everything is experienced in time. This applies to our internal selves as well as to all external objects. Since categories are the forms through which every specific thing can be thought as being in time, categories are related to time. Thus, pure concepts, or categories, and phenomenal objects share time as a common feature. Therefore, time is the means by which an intuited phenomenon is subsumed under a pure concept. Schemata are transcendental time determinations. "Hence it will be possible for the category to be applied to appearances by means of the transcendental time determination, which, as the schema of the concepts of the understanding, mediates the subsumption of appearances under the category."[32]

Schemata are procedural rules, not images

Because schemata are determinations of objects in general, not specific, individual objects, they are not particular images. Kant asserted that "… a schema must be distinguished from an image."[33] A schema is a procedural rule.[34] The rule prescribes the way to relate a pure concept to an object in general. Schemata are ways of applying pure concepts (categories) to sense impressions. They are prescriptions for graphically illustrating a pure concept. A schema is a method for representing a non-empirical concept in any image as such or any image in general. "… [T]his representation of a general procedure of the imagination for providing a concept with its image, I call the schema of such a concept."[35] " … [F]or Kant a schema is not an image, but a capacity to form images or (perhaps) to construct models."[36] "The schema of a pure concept of the understanding is something which can never be made into an image..."[37]

Lewis White Beck[38] wrote, "The pure concepts of the understanding…are applied to the pure form of intuition (time) to give rise to the 'transcendental schemata' or rules of the application of pure concepts to whatever sense–impressions we receive." To exemplify this, he continued, "To take the most important example, we have the hypothetical (if–then) judgment, which is the mode of judgment under the category of cause. This is applied to phenomena in time by the schema of causation, namely, the rule that the cause of a phenomenon is another phenomenon that invariably precedes it in time…." In this way, Beck showed that a transcendental schema is the rule that leads to the understanding of successive [in time] sensations according to various pure concepts [Kant's "categories"].

Illustrations of Different categories and their schemata

Each category has one schema. Some schemas are shared by other categories in their class.[39]

Even though Kant provided these illustrations and examples of schemata, author John Mahaffy claimed that the topic remained obscure. He wrote, "I may add, that these illustrations of the various schemata are developed and explained by the succeeding chapters on the Principles which embody them, and that it is impossible to make them clear to the reader until he has studied the theory of the Principles."[47]

Schematized and unschematized categories

The schemata give the categories a "cash value",[48] as though the category is like paper money and sense experience is analogous to precious metal. A schema is the agreement or harmony of a category with sensual phenomena. For example, "Number is the quantity of the phenomenon; sensation is the reality of the phenomenon; the permanence and endurance of things is the substance of the phenomenon, eternity is the necessity of the phenomenon, etc."[49] In this way, the schemata restrict the categories to conditions of sensibility. "Schematism and the schemas thus have the property of 'realizing' the categories at the same time as restricting their scope to appearances."[50] Categories cannot be realized in objects that are not detectable by the senses, that is, are not phenomenal objects or objects that appear to an observer.

"The schemata of the pure concepts of the understanding are, therefore, the true and sole conditions for providing these concepts with a reference to objects and hence with signification. And therefore the categories have, in the end, no other use than a possible empirical one."[51] In order for categories to refer to perceived, experienced objects, they must be schematized. If a category is not schematized, then it has no reference to perception. An unschematized category can be thought, but can not be known. If something can never be perceived, it can never be known. Schemata represent things in general as they appear, not as they might otherwise exist. "Categories, therefore, without schemata are only functions[52] of the understanding necessary for concepts, but do not themselves represent any object."[53] With the transcendental determination of time as the transcendental schema, " … use of the categories is clearly restricted to the range of things that fall within time — meaning, for Kant, restricted to phenomena."[54] Metaphysical entities that are not related to time, such as spontaneous or uncaused movements, immortal souls, and eternal gods, are products of unschematized categories. They can be thought, but not known.

Alternative schemata

Kant said that the schema of a concept is the representation of a general procedure of the imagination by which an image can be supplied for a concept.[11] Kant claimed that time is the only proper and appropriate transcendental schema because it shares the a priori category's generality and purity as well as any a posteriori phenomenon's manner of appearance. However, it may be true that time is not the only possible schema.

Space

"Even more remarkable, however, is the fact that in order to understand the possibility of things as consequent upon the categories, and hence in order to establish the categories' objective reality, we need not merely intuitions but indeed always outer intuitions."[55] Since space is the form of all appearances of the outer senses, it may seem that space could serve as a schema. Indeed, any phenomenon that requires space, as well as time, as a form would also need a spatial schema. "This suggests that he may have thought at one point of recasting the Schematism argument in a fundamental way, by substituting space for time; but if he had this idea, he did not carry it out."[48] In the editor's introduction to his translation of the Critique,[56] Paul Guyer asserted that "…although the content of the transcendental schemata for the categories may be explicated in purely temporal terms, the use of these schemata in turn depends upon judgments about the spatial properties and relations of at least some objects of empirical judgment." Guyer claimed that this declaration was clarified in Kant's "The System of All Principles" section.[57] In this way, the use of schemata is supposed to involve both space and time, instead of merely time.

Organism

In order to show how time may not be the only schema, Professor Walsh suggested that there is "… the possibility of making sense of the categories in organic as opposed to mechanical terms."[48] He hypothesized that "Elements in an organic complex would here take the place of elements in a temporal situation. Substance might be interpreted in terms of growth and form as opposed to what underlies mechanical change, and causality be thought of in terms of purpose and function."[48] However, Professor Walsh concluded that Kant's choice of time as schema was more precise than any alternative choices. In spite of the general difficulty in understanding Schematism, he asserted that "… Kant's doctrine of schematism, if not altogether satisfactory at the theoretical level, will continue to stand on the strong empirical ground that the schemata offered do enable us to give real meaning to the categories and find for them a genuine use."[48]

Schemata of systematic unity

In his discussion of the Architectonic of Pure Reason,[58] Kant utilized the concept of schema in a way that was similar to his discussion of the schemata of the Categories. A science's whole systematic organization consists of parts. The parts are various cognitions or units of knowledge. The parts are united under one idea which determines the relation of the parts to each other and also the purpose of the whole system. A schema is needed to execute, carry out, or realize this unifying idea and put it into effect. This schema is a sketch or outline of the way that the parts of knowledge are organized into a whole system of science. A schema which is sketched, designed, or drafted in accordance with accidental, empirical purposes results in mere technical unity. But a schema that is drawn up from an a priori rational idea is the foundational outline of architectonic unity. Science must have architectonic unity. "For the schema of what we call science must contain the whole's outline (monogramma) and the whole's division into parts in conformity with the idea — i.e., it must contain these a priori — and must distinguish this whole from all others with certainty and according to principles."[59] This use of the concept of schema is similar to Kant's previous use. It is a minimal outline, monogram, or diagram that realizes or executes an abstract, general concept or idea (Idee) as actual, perceptual experience.

Critical views

Obscurity of the concept "Schema"

Kant introduced the concept of the transcendental schema in his chapter entitled "Of the Schematism of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding."[60] It is considered to be one of Kant's more difficult chapters. Even though he knew that he was not writing for a popular readership, Kant twice tried to apologize for this chapter by calling it "very dry"[61] and "dry and tedious."[62] Professor W.H. Walsh, of the University of Edinburgh, wrote: "The chapter on Schematism probably presents more difficulties to the uncommitted but sympathetic reader than any other part of the Critique of Pure Reason. Not only are the details of the argument highly obscure (that, after all, is a common enough experience in reading Kant, though one is not often so baffled as one is here): it is hard to say in plain terms what general point or points Kant is seeking to establish."[63] Schopenhauer referred to it as "…the strange 'Chapter on the Schematism of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding,' which is well known for its great obscurity, since no one has ever been able to make anything out of it."[64] Schopenhauer's notebooks contained entries that described Kant's chapter on schemata as "an audacious piece of nonsense"[65] and the schema as "an absurdity whose non–existence is plain."[66] In Schopenhauer's criticism of Kant's schemata, he attempted to clear up the obscurity by attributing Kant's concept of schemata simply to a psychological need for architectonic symmetry in his writings.[67] Empirical concepts are based on empirical perceptions. Kant, however, tried to claim that, analogously, pure concepts (Categories) also have a basis. But this contradicts his previous assertion that pure concepts simply exist in the human mind and are not based on pure, schematic perceptions. Schopenhauer also alleged that schemata were introduced merely to give plausibility to Kant's description of the categories or pure concepts of the understanding. The article on Kant in the Encyclopedia of Philosophy calls Kant's schematism a "baffling doctrine " with "cryptic sentences."[68] Josiah Royce referred to "the perplexing doctrine of the Schema."[69] The Scottish philosopher Robert Adamson wrote: "Kant's manner of explaining the functions of schematism is extremely apt to be misunderstood, and to mislead."[70] Kant's early critics (1782 –1789) did not discuss schematism because they couldn't follow Kant's explanation.[71] After more than two centuries, Kant's explanation of schema still seems to be unclear to many readers. In their book on Parallel distributed processing, the PDP Research Group discussed Kant's schemata when they appropriated that word to designate their concept of image schemata. "The schema," they wrote, "throughout history, has been a concept shrouded in mystery. Kant's … use of the term has been provocative but difficult to understand."[72] After this sentence, no further attempt was made to discuss Kant's term and the concept that it designates.

Discrepancies

According to Professor W. H. Walsh, there is an apparent discrepancy in Kant's central arguments about schematism. Kant, according to Professor Walsh, first claimed that empirical concepts do not require schemata. Only pure concepts need schemata in order to be realized.[73] This is because pure concepts are totally different from intuitions, whereas, empirical concepts are abstracted from intuitions and are therefore homogeneous with them. But in another part of his chapter, Kant states that mathematical concepts have schemata. "In fact," he wrote, "it is schemata, not images of objects, that lie at the basis of our pure sensible (i.e., geometrical) concepts."[74] In discussing schematism as the method of representing in one image a certain mathematical quantity according to a certain concept, he wrote: "This representation of a general procedure of the imagination by which a concept receives its image, I call the schema of such concept."[75] With regard to pure concepts, Kant then declares, "The schema of a pure concept of the understanding, on the contrary, is something which can never be made into an image … ."[76]

Kant, according to Professor Walsh, has two distinct ways of describing schemata. "Sometimes, as at the beginning of his discussion, he speaks as if a schema were a feature of things which could be pointed to … .[73] In another place, Kant " … speaks as if schematism were a procedure … ."[77]

Problematic mediation

According to Kant, a transcendental schema is a mediating nexus, a third thing, between a pure concept and a phenomenon.[78] This mediation was never satisfactorily explained by Kant, and Charles Sanders Peirce declared that it is a major part of Kant's system. Kant's "doctrine of the schemata can only have been an afterthought…," Peirce wrote.[79] The theory of mediating schemata was "an addition to his system after it was substantially complete."[80] The enormous importance of the concept of the transcendental schema was emphasized by Peirce when he wrote that "if the schemata had been considered early enough, they would have overgrown his whole work."[81]

Adamson's interpretation

Scottish philosopher Robert Adamson wrote from a Hegelian standpoint. He believed that Kant's analysis of knowledge into the separate topics of intuition, schema, and concept was mechanical and artificial. Adamson claimed that "Thought and Intuition are organically united in the schema."[70] "We are not to suppose that the subsumption [of the intuition under the pure notion] is mechanical; that the particular is something distinct from the universal. The union is organic; the particular is only the universal under a special form. The same function of synthesis, which in pure abstraction we call category, is, in realization, the schema, and the intuition is not apart from the schema."[82] Kant's abstract analysis of perceptual knowledge was, according to Adamson, the misleading separation of an organic unity into individual components. He asserted that "… we must on no account regard Notion, Schema, and Intuition, as three parts of perception which would exist in isolation."[83] This amalgamation is typical of the Hegelian "dialectical" formula in which two apparent opposites are always subsumed or reconciled by some third entity.

Pluhar's interpretation

In the translator's introduction to his version of Kant's Critique of Judgment, page xxxvi, Werner Pluhar tried to explain schemata. He noted that perceptual intuitions and Kant's conceptual categories are very different, yet they relate to each other. This exposition by Professor Pluhar paraphrases Kant's doctrine that perceptions are based on concepts. Kant's position can be contrasted with Schopenhauer's opposite teaching that concepts are derived or abstracted from perceptions, thereby giving content to the concepts and allowing them to make sense. This is the very reason why pure concepts, or categories, require schemata. "Something is needed," Pluhar wrote, sharing Kant's viewpoint, "to mediate between intuition in general and the categories, viz., a rule or 'schema' that stipulates what conditions the intuition must meet so that it can match a category." Professor Pluhar then gave a specific example of how time is utilized to accomplish the matching or mediation. His explanation does not resort to presenting schemata through the use of visual analogies such as "sketches" or "outlines." Pluhar's schemata are rules. "In the case of causal relation, the schema is the rule that the effect must follow the cause in time." After providing this particular instance, he declared generally that "…all schemata connect the categories with time…." Professor Pluhar then asserted the reason for this schematic connection: "…time is the only form of intuition that applies to any intuition whatsoever, even to the inner intuition that we have of ourselves, whereas space applies merely to all outer intuitions." Oddly enough, schemata do not have to be added as mediators to the categories of causality and substance. These are already temporalized. Time is intrinsic to the relation between cause and effect. Substance, by its very nature, is a thing that continually endures.

Elaborations of Kant's notion of schema in cognitive science

The philosopher Mark Johnson discusses Kant's conception of a schema with respect to developing a theory of the imagination within cognitive science.[84] Johnson's theory makes use of Kant's insights that analogy is the cognitive mechanism which links sensible percepts to their conceptual categories, and that creative analogy—or what Johnson calls conceptual metaphor—is the cognitive mechanism by which we come to have our understanding of those abstract concepts and categories of which we have less direct sensible experience. He proposes that we use imaginative schemata to structure abstract concepts largely in terms a set of spatial analogies he calls image schemata. In Johnson's view, we acquire image schemata primarily from recurrent patterns of experiences in infancy and early childhood, and then reuse these image schemata in a metaphoric fashion both to reason abstractly and as we speak our language.

In an increase of ambiguity and confusion, some cognitive scientists today have appropriated the often–misused technical term "schema" to mean Kantian Category. In his book Cognitive-Behavioral Therapy: Basic Principles and Applications (Jason Aronson Publishers,1996), Robert L. Leahy of the American Institute for Cognitive Therapy in New York City and the Weill Cornell Medical College of Cornell University exemplifies this misuse. In Chapter 2, "Historical Context of Cognitive Therapy," he wrote of how, for Kant, "reality is never directly knowable, but rather is 'known' through 'categories of thinking.'" Leahy then stated, "According to Kant, all knowledge was based on the 'categories' (which today we would call schemas). Consequently, reality was never directly knowable--we only knew the schemas." In this way, Kant's concept of "category," or "pure concept of the understanding," is no longer defined as being a predicate, property, quality, or characteristic of any and all objects in general. A Kantian Category is now vaguely considered by cognitive scientists to be a "schema," which was a term that Kant had already used to designate the subsumption of an empirical intuition, through time, under a category or pure concept.

References

  1. ^ For an explanation of the logical structure of this progression, see Stephen Palmquist, "The Architectonic Form of Kant's Copernican Logic", Metaphilosophy 17:4 (October 1986), pp.266-288; revised and reprinted as Chapter III of Stephen Palmquist, Kant's System of Perspectives: An architectonic interpretation of the Critical philosophy (Lanham: University Press of America, 1993). Also see the third Appendix entitled, "Common Objections to Architectonic Reasoning.
  2. ^ Ellington, James W., "The Unity of Kant's Thought in His Philosophy of Corporeal Nature," Philosophy of Material Nature
  3. ^ Walsh, W.H., "Schematism," Kant-Studien, Band 49
  4. ^ A schema is related to a perceived object as a single letter is related to a whole name.
  5. ^ A priori concepts, or Categories, "require, in order to be meaningful and significant, a certain concrete use — that is, an application to some intuition by which an object of them is given to us." Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, § 8.
  6. ^ Walsh, W.H., "Schematism," Kant-Studien, vol. 49
  7. ^ Critique of Pure Reason A137
  8. ^ Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, Vol. I, Appendix, "Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy", p. 449 f.
  9. ^ a b c d Critique of Judgment, § 59
  10. ^ Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, Vol. I, Appendix, "Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy", p. 449
  11. ^ a b Critique of Pure Reason, A 140
  12. ^ a b Critique of Pure Reason, A 141
  13. ^ a b Critique of Pure Reason, A 51
  14. ^ Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, Vol. I., Appendix, "Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy. p. 449
  15. ^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Volume 3, "Kant, Immanuel"
  16. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A 142
  17. ^ Ellington, James W., "The Unity of Kant's Thought in His Philosophy of Corporeal Nature," Part 3
  18. ^ Walsh, W. H., "Schematism", Kant-Studien, Band 49 (1957)
  19. ^ Ellington, James W., "The Unity of Kant's Thought in His Philosophy of Corporeal Nature," Part 3
  20. ^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Volume 3, "Kant, Immanuel"
  21. ^ Ellington, James W., "The Unity of Kant's Thought in His Philosophy of Corporeal Nature," Part 3
  22. ^ Critique of Pure Reason A81
  23. ^ Critique of Pure Reason A 139
  24. ^ Körner, S., Kant, p. 71ff.
  25. ^ Critique of Pure Reason A 51
  26. ^ Körner, S., Kant, Chapter 4, p. 70 f.
  27. ^ Körner, S., Kant, p. 72
  28. ^ Critique of Pure Reason A 132
  29. ^ First Introduction to the Critique of Judgment, § V, 212
  30. ^ First Introduction to the Critique of Judgment, § V, 214
  31. ^ Critique of Pure Reason A 136
  32. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A139
  33. ^ Ibid. A140
  34. ^ "The schema is not an image, because the image is a product of the reproductive imagination, while the schema of sensible concepts (also of figures in space) is a product of the pure a priori capacity to imagine…" (Umberto Eco, Kant and the Platypus, Harcourt, 1999, § 2.5). Eco compared a Kantian schema to Peano axioms, Wittgenstein's concept of Bild [a proposition that has the same "form" as the fact that it represents], and a computer programming flowchart. In this way, it is a procedural rule that provides instructions regarding the construction of a sensible intuition from an abstract, general concept. See also Diego Marconi, Lexical Competence, MIT Press, 1997, pp. 146 ff.
  35. ^ Ibid.
  36. ^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Volume 3, "Kant, Immanuel"
  37. ^ Critique of Pure Reason A 142
  38. ^ Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, Editor's Introduction," Bobbs-Merrill Co., 1950.
  39. ^ Critique of Pure Reason A143
  40. ^ a b William H.S. Monck, Introduction to the Critical Philosophy, p. 43.
  41. ^ William H.S. Monck, Introduction to the Critical Philosophy, p. 43 f.
  42. ^ a b c d William H.S. Monck, Introduction to the Critical Philosophy, p. 44.
  43. ^ William H.S. Monck, Introduction to the Critical Philosophy, p.44.
  44. ^ a b William H.S. Monck, Introduction to the Critical Philosophy, p. 45.
  45. ^ Ellington, James W., "The Unity of Kant's Thought in His Philosophy of Corporeal Nature," Part 3
  46. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A145
  47. ^ Kant's Critical Philosophy for English Readers, John P. Mahaffy, Note to page 263.
  48. ^ a b c d e Walsh, W.H., "Schematism"
  49. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A 146
  50. ^ Howard Caygill, A Kant Dictionary, "Schema(tism)"
  51. ^ Ibid. A146
  52. ^ By function, Kant means "… the unity of the act of ordering various representations under a common representation."Critique of Pure Reason, A 68. This act results in the formation of one abstract concept from various perceptions or other concepts.
  53. ^ Ibid. A147
  54. ^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Volume 3, "Kant, Immanuel"
  55. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, B291
  56. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, Cambridge University Press, 2000, p. 10
  57. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, B 188 ff.
  58. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A 832
  59. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A 834
  60. ^ Critique of Pure Reason A 137
  61. ^ Prolegomena to any future metaphysics, § 34
  62. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A 142
  63. ^ Walsh, W.H., "Schematism," Kant–Studien, Band 49 (1957), Kölner Universitäts–Verlag
  64. ^ Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, Vol. I, Appendix, "Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy", p. 450
  65. ^ "…from the chapter on the schematism of the pure concepts of the understanding (a chapter which, in spite of all our respect for Kant, we must call an audacious piece of nonsense) it is very clear that these categories not only contribute nothing towards intuitive perception, but are very far removed from this, since there are still to be found between them and intuitive perception these quite peculiar absurdities, the schemata." Schopenhauer, Manuscript Remains, Vol. 2, "Against Kant," p. 466.
  66. ^ "There is … inserted between the categories and intuitive perception the schema, an absurdity whose non–existence is plain to anyone in his senses…." Schopenhauer, Manuscript Remains, Vol. 2, "Against Kant," p. 472.
  67. ^

    …here more than anywhere else do the intentional nature of Kant's method of procedure and the resolve, arrived at beforehand, to find what would correspond to the analogy, and what might assist the architectonic symmetry, clearly come to light. … By assuming schemata of the pure (void of content) concepts a priori of the understanding (categories) analogous to the empirical schemata (or representatives of our actual concepts through the imagination), he overlooks the fact that the purpose of such schemata is here entirely wanting. The purpose of the schemata in the case of empirical (actual) thinking is related solely to the material content of such concepts. Since these concepts are drawn from empirical perception, we assist ourselves and see where we are, in the case of abstract thinking, by casting now and then a fleeting, retrospective glance at perception from which the concepts are taken, in order to assure ourselves that our thinking still has real content. This, however, necessarily presupposes that the concepts which occupy us have sprung from perception…. But with concepts a priori, which have no content at all, obviously this is of necessity omitted because these have not sprung from perception, but come to it from within, in order first to receive a content from it.

    Ibid.

  68. ^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Volume 3, "Kant, Immanuel"
  69. ^ Lectures on Modern Idealism, Lecture II, p. 57
  70. ^ a b Robert Adamson, On the Philosophy of Kant, p. 53 f.
  71. ^ "It was not clear what the link was between categories and intuitions and how empty forms of the understanding could be applied to sensations. Kant was aware of this problem and tried to address it through the doctrine of the schematism, but his contemporaries were not able to follow him here. Indeed, the doctrine of the schematism was left largely out of consideration by Kant's critics." Kant's Early Critics, Edited by Brigitte Sassen, Cambridge University Press, 2007, p. 30.
  72. ^ McClelland, J.L., et al., Parallel Distributed Processing, Vol. 2, p. 17
  73. ^ a b Walsh, W. H. , "Schematism", Kant–Studien, Band 49 (1957)
  74. ^ Critique of Pure Reason A141
  75. ^ Critique of Pure Reason A140
  76. ^ Critique of Pure Reason A142
  77. ^ Ibid.
  78. ^ Critique of Pure Reason, A138
  79. ^ Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vol. I, page 35
  80. ^ Ibid.
  81. ^ Ibid.
  82. ^ Robert Adamson, On the Philosophy of Kant, p. 54.
  83. ^ Robert Adamson, On the Philosophy of Kant, p. 55.
  84. ^ The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination, and Reason, pp. 147-172

Bibliography

See also