In mathematics, a cardinal number κ is called huge if there exists an elementary embedding j : V → M from V into a transitive inner model M with critical point κ and
Here, αM is the class of all sequences of length α whose elements are in M.
Huge cardinals were introduced by Kenneth Kunen (1978).
Contents |
In what follows, jn refers to the n-th iterate of the elementary embedding j, that is, j composed with itself n times, for a finite ordinal n. Also, <αM is the class of all sequences of length less than α whose elements are in M. Notice that for the "super" versions, γ should be less than j(κ), not .
κ is almost n-huge if and only if there is j : V → M with critical point κ and
κ is super almost n-huge if and only if for every ordinal γ there is j : V → M with critical point κ, γ<j(κ), and
κ is n-huge if and only if there is j : V → M with critical point κ and
κ is super n-huge if and only if for every ordinal γ there is j : V → M with critical point κ, γ<j(κ), and
Notice that 0-huge is the same as measurable cardinal; and 1-huge is the same as huge. A cardinal satisfying one of the rank into rank axioms is n-huge for all finite n.
The existence of an almost huge cardinal implies that Vopenka's principle is consistent; more precisely any almost huge cardinal is also a Vopenka cardinal.
The cardinals are arranged in order of increasing consistency strength as follows:
The consistency of a huge cardinal implies the consistency of a supercompact cardinal, nevertheless, the least huge cardinal is smaller than the least supercompact cardinal (assuming both exist).
One can try defining an ω-huge cardinal κ as one such that an elementary embedding j : V → M from V into a transitive inner model M with critical point κ and λM⊆M, where λ is the supremum of jnκ for positive integers n. However Kunen's inconsistency theorem shows that ω-huge cardinals are inconsistent in ZFC, though it is still open whether they are consistent in ZF.