Theological fatalism
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
This article or section may contain original research or unverified claims. Please improve the article by adding references. See the talk page for details. (March 2008) |
This article does not cite any references or sources. (March 2008) Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources. Unverifiable material may be challenged and removed. |
Theological fatalism is the view that all our actions are pre-determined because of God's forknowledge of them, and that therefore we have no free will[1][2]. A related attempt to demonstrate a logical contradiction between an omniscient God and free will is discussed in the Argument from free will.
The argument is roughly stated as follows:
- God is omniscient.
- Since God is omniscient, God has infallible foreknowledge.
- If God has infallible foreknowledge that tomorrow you will engage in event X, then you must invariably engage in event X.
- You must invariably engage in event X.
Therefore, free-will is not possible since you have no alternative except to engage in event X. In the event that you do not fulfil event X, then God is not omniscient. Alternatively, if you engage in event X, then you don't have free-will on account of the inability to choose another alternative.
However, the premises contain some logical flaws and circular logic. First, premise 4 does not logically follow from the earlier premises, since no premise states that God has infallible foreknowledge that tomorrow you will engage in event X. Premise 3 states what will occur if that were true, but no premise actually asserts that knowledge.
Secondly, premise 3 assumes what is trying to be proven. In an argument trying to prove that foreknowledge of X logically leads to having to do X, premise 3 simply states this outright. If you accept premise 3, then technically you don’t even need the other premises, because premise 3 states the conclusion that it is attempting to prove. Thus, the argument is a case of circular logic, and is therefore invalid.
An opposing argument can state:
- God is omniscient
- Since God is omniscient, He is also infallible.
- If God has infallible foreknowledge that tomorrow you will engage in event X, then you will freely choose this based on your free will, not obligation or lack of choice in event X.
- You still have free will to engage in event X; God merely knows your choice before you make it. You are not obliged to make choice 'X' anymore than choice 'A'. If you were going to change your mind, God would have seen that also, so you still have full free will in all matters. Also, you will still make the same choices [with free will] even if God chose to not see the future. Seeing the future or not does not alter your free will.
With passive foreknowledge, if it were kept hidden, it would not invalidate free will in any logical or rational way. The individual choosing event X, would be making the exact same choices regardless of whether God knew the choices beforehand or not. God knowing or not knowing the future [passively] would not alter the free will of individuals at all. The demise of free will would only logically come if God made His knowledge public in regard to the free will choice of individuals; this would therefore alter future free will, and make it an obligation. One simple illustration could be a psychic person foreseeing someone the other side of the world tripping and breaking their leg when they run to catch a bus. The psychic would not be altering reality be foreseeing this event, as this event would still happen regardless of whether someone has seen it or not, the same application can be applied to God's omniscience, as long as it is passive, and non-interfering with reality or other's knowledge of it, then it is not contravening the free will of humans.
However, if it is to be understood that God created all that is created, the principle asserts that this poses a problem for any passive knowledge on God's part. An understanding of omniscience must be joined with an understanding of God's omnipresence in time. If God knows all events past, future, and present then he would know all events and decisions an individual would make though from the individuals perspective those events and decisions have not yet occurred. This can be viewed, at least implicitly, as a nullification of any concept of free will for any individual though no mechanism for God's apparent foreknowledge restraining the freedom to act of the individual is posited by the principle of theological fatalism. Since, according to the Christian theology, God is atemporal (existing outside of time), God knows from creation the entire course of one's life, all the actions in which he will partake, and even whether or not that individual will accept his divine authority. With these preconditions, only a starkly fatalist theological position seems imaginable to some.
Alternatively, if God can see the future like it was past history like reading a past infinite almanac, then He (as long as He didn’t tell anyone or influence their choices) would not be responsible for the outcomes anymore then if He'd never looked.
The problem with the arguments against theological fatalism is that they don't take into account the supposed perfection of the god, or the inability to be truly wrong (which contradicts omnipotence). If god knows the future, then in any case the future that he knows must occur, whether he ignores the future or not. If a different outcome occurs, that would mean the foreknowledge of god would be wrong, therefore nullifying his perfection.
If said god would exist, and it came to pass that a human surprised him, or contradicted his knowledge by not making the decision that god thought he would, it would ultimately show god to have (had) some weakness to mankind. Humans would not be free to choose, because they can only choose what god already knows they will choose. It is not only a matter of what god knows, but also his supposed perfection, and whether he can be wrong. His (in)ability to be wrong also questions god's omnipotence, since one can't be perfect while retaining the ability to be wrong.
[edit] Notes and References
- ^ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Foreknowledge and Free Will
- ^ Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Foreknowledge and Free Will