Stone–Čech compactification
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
In the mathematical discipline of general topology, Stone–Čech compactification is a technique for constructing a universal map from a topological space X to a compact Hausdorff space βX. The Stone–Čech compactification βX of a topological space X is the largest compact Hausdorff space "generated" by X, in the sense that any map from X to a compact Hausdorff space factors through βX (in a unique way). If X is a Tychonoff space then the map from X to its image in βX is a homeomorphism, so X can be thought of as a (dense) subspace of βX. For general topological spaces X, the map from X to βX need not be injective.
A form of the axiom of choice is required to prove that every topological space has a Stone–Čech compactification. Even for quite simple spaces X, an accessible concrete description of βX often remains elusive. In particular it is impossible to explicitly exhibit a point in .
The Stone–Čech compactification was found by Marshall Stone (1937) and Eduard Čech (1937).
Contents |
[edit] Universal property and functoriality
βX is a compact Hausdorff space together with a continuous map from X and has the following universal property: any continuous map f : X → K, where K is a compact Hausdorff space, lifts uniquely to a continuous map βf : βX → K.
As is usual for universal properties, this universal property, together with the fact that βX is a compact Hausdorff space containing X, characterizes βX up to homeomorphism.
Some authors add the assumption that the starting space be Tychonoff (or even locally compact Hausdorff), for the following reasons:
- The map from X to its image in βX is a homeomorphism if and only if X is Tychonoff.
- The map from X to its image in βX is a homeomorphism to an open subspace if and only if X is locally compact Hausdorff.
The Stone–Čech construction can be performed for more general spaces X, but the map X → βX need not be a homeomorphism to the image of X (and sometimes is not even injective).
The extension property makes β a functor from Top (the category of topological spaces) to CHaus (the category of compact Hausdorff spaces). If we let U be the inclusion functor from CHaus into Top, maps from βX to K (for K in CHaus) correspond bijectively to maps from X to UK (by considering their restriction to X and using the universal property of βX). i.e. Hom(βX,K) = Hom(X,UK), which means that β is left adjoint to U. This implies that CHaus is a reflective subcategory of Top with reflector β.
[edit] Constructions
[edit] Construction using products
One attempt to construct the Stone-Cech compactification of X is to take the closure of the image of X in
where the product is over all maps from X to compact Hausdorff spaces C. This works "formally" but fails for the technical reason that the collection of all such maps is a proper class rather than a set. There are several ways to modify this idea to make it work; for example, one can restrict the compact Hausdorff spaces C to have underlying set P(P(X)) (the power set of the power set of X), which is sufficiently large that it has cardinality at least equal to that of every compact Hausdorff set to which X can be mapped with dense image.
[edit] Construction using the unit interval
One way of constructing βX is to consider the map
where C is the set of all continuous functions from X into [0,1]. This may be seen to be a continuous map onto its image, if [0,1]C is given the product topology. By Tychonoff's theorem we have that [0,1]C is compact since [0,1] is, so the closure of X in [0,1]C is a compactification of X.
In order to verify that this is the Stone–Čech compactification, we just need to verify that it satisfies the appropriate universal property. We do this first for K = [0,1], where the desired extension of f : X → [0,1] is just the projection onto the f coordinate in [0,1]C. In order to then get this for general compact Hausdorff K we use the above to note that K can be embedded in some cube, extend each of the coordinate functions and then take the product of these extensions.
The special property of the unit interval needed for this construction to work is that it is a cogenerator of the category of compact Hausdorff spaces: this means that if f and g are any two distinct maps from compact Hausdorff spaces A to B, then there is a map h from B to [0,1] such that hf and hg are distinct. Any other cogenerator (or cogenerating set) can be used in this construction.
[edit] Construction using ultrafilters
Alternatively, if X is discrete, one can construct βX as the set of all ultrafilters on X, with a topology known as Stone topology. The elements of X correspond to the principal ultrafilters.
Again we verify the universal property: For f : X → K with K compact Hausdorff and F an ultrafilter on X we have an ultrafilter f(F) on K. This has a unique limit because K is compact, say x, and we define βf(F) = x. This may be verified to be a continuous extension of f.
Equivalently, one can take the Stone space of the complete Boolean algebra of all subsets of X as the Stone–Čech compactification. This is really the same construction, as the Stone space of this Boolean algebra is the set of ultrafilters (or equivalently prime ideals, or homomorphisms to the 2 element Boolean algebra) of the Boolean algebra, which is the same as the set of ultrafilters on X.
The construction can be generalized to arbitrary Tychonoff spaces by using maximal filters of zero sets instead of ultrafilters. (Filters of closed sets suffice if the space is normal.)
[edit] Construction using C*-algebras
In case X is a completely regular Hausdorff space, the Stone-Čech compactification can be identified with the spectrum of M(Cb(X)). Here Cb(X) denotes the C*-algebra of all continuous bounded functions on X with sup-norm, and M(Cb(X)) denotes its multiplier algebra.
[edit] The Stone–Čech compactification of the natural numbers
In the case where X is locally compact, e.g. or , it forms an open subset of βX, or indeed of any compactification, (this is also a necessary condition, as an open subset of a compact Hausdorff space is locally compact). In this case one often studies the remainder of the space, . This is a closed subset of βX, and so is compact. We consider with its discrete topology and write (but this does not appear to be standard notation for general X).
One can view as the set of ultrafilters on , with the topology generated by sets of the form for . corresponds to the set of principal ultrafilters, and to the set of free ultrafilters.
The easiest way to see this is isomorphic to is to show that it satisfies the universal property. For with K compact Hausdorff and F an ultrafilter on we have an ultrafilter f(F) on K, the pushforward of F. This has a unique limit, say x, because K is compact Hausdorff, and we define βf(F) = x. This may readily be verified to be a continuous extension.
(A similar but slightly more involved construction of the Stone–Čech compactification as a set of certain maximal filters can also be given for a general Tychonoff space X.)
The study of βN, and in particular , is a major area of modern set theoretic topology. The major results motivating this are Parovicenko's theorems, essentially characterising its behaviour under the assumption of the continuum hypothesis.
These state:
- Every compact Hausdorff space of weight at most (see Aleph number) is the continuous image of (this does not need the continuum hypothesis, but is less interesting in its absence).
- If the continuum hypothesis holds then is the unique Parovicenko space, up to isomorphism.
These were originally proved by considering Boolean algebras and applying Stone duality.
Jan van Mill has described as a 'three headed monster' - the three heads being a smiling and friendly head (the behaviour under the assumption of the continuum hypothesis), the ugly head of independence which constantly tries to confuse you (determining what behaviour is possible in different models of set theory), and the third head is the smallest of all (what you can prove about it in ZFC). It has relatively recently been observed that this characterisation isn't quite right - there is in fact a fourth head of , in which forcing axioms and Ramsey type axioms give properties of almost diametrically opposed to those under the continuum hypothesis, giving very few maps from indeed. Examples of these axioms include the combination of Martin's axiom and the Open colouring axiom which, for example, prove that , while the continuum hypothesis implies the opposite.
[edit] An application: the dual space of the space of bounded sequences of reals
The Stone–Čech compactification βN can be used to characterize (the Banach space of all bounded sequences in the scalar field R or C, with supremum norm) and its dual space.
Given a bounded sequence , there exists a closed ball B that contains the image of a (B is a subset of the scalar field). a is then a function from to B. Since is discrete and B is compact and Hausdorff, a is continuous. According to the universal property, there exists a unique extension . This extension does not depend on the ball B we consider.
We have defined an extension map from the space of bounded scalar valued sequences to the space of continuous functions over .
This map is bijective since every function in must be bounded and can then be restricted to a bounded scalar sequence.
If we further consider both spaces with the sup norm the extension map becomes an isometry. Indeed, if in the construction above we take the smallest possible ball B, we see that the sup norm of the extended sequence does not grow (although the image of the extended function can be bigger).
Thus, can be identified with . This allows us to use the Riesz representation theorem and find that the dual space of can be identified with the space of finite Borel measures on .
Finally, it should be noticed that this technique generalizes to the space of an arbitrary measure space X. However, instead of simply considering the space βX of ultrafilters on X, the right way to generalize this construction is to consider the Stone space Y of the measure algebra of X: the spaces C(Y) and are isomorphic as C*-algebras as long as X satisfies a reasonable finiteness condition (that any set of positive measure contains a subset of finite positive measure).
[edit] Addition on the Stone–Čech compactification of the naturals
The natural numbers form a monoid under addition. It turns out that this operation can be extended (in more than one way) to , turning this space also into a monoid, though rather surprisingly a non-commutative one.
For any subset and , we define
Given two ultrafilters F and G on , we define their sum by
it can be checked that this is again an ultrafilter, and that the operation + is associative (but not commutative) on and extends the addition on ; 0 serves as a neutral element for the operation + on . The operation is also right-continuous, in the sense that for every ultrafilter F, the map
is continuous.
[edit] See also
[edit] External links
- Stone-Čech compactification on PlanetMath
- Dror Bar-Natan, Ultrafilters, Compactness, and the Stone–Čech compactification
[edit] References
- Čech, E. (1937), “On bicompact spaces”, Ann. of Math. 38: 823–844, <http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0003-486X%28193710%292%3A38%3A4%3C823%3AOBS%3E2.0.CO%3B2-P>
- Hindman, Neil & Strauss, Dona (1998), Algebra in the Stone-Cech compactification. Theory and applications, vol. 27, de Gruyter Expositions in Mathematics, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co., pp. xiv+485 pp., MR1642231, ISBN 3-11-015420-X
- Koshevnikova, I.G. (2001), “Stone–Čech compactification”, in Hazewinkel, Michiel, Encyclopaedia of Mathematics, Kluwer Academic Publishers, ISBN 978-1556080104
- Stone, M.H. (1937), “Applications of the theory of Boolean rings to general topology”, Trans. Amer. Soc. 41: 375–481, <http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0002-9947%28193705%2941%3A3%3C375%3AAOTTOB%3E2.0.CO%3B2-8>