Later-no-harm criterion
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
The later-no-harm criterion is a voting system criterion formulated by Douglas Woodall. The criterion is satisfied if, in any election, a voter giving an additional ranking or positive rating to a less preferred candidate cannot cause a more preferred candidate to lose.
Contents |
[edit] Complying methods
Single transferable vote, Minimax Condorcet, and Descending Solid Coalitions, a variant of Woodall's Descending Acquiescing Coalitions rule, satisfy the later-no-harm criterion.
However, if a method permits incomplete ranking of candidates, and if a majority of votes is required for election, it cannot satisfy Later-no-harm, because a lower preference vote cast may create a majority for that lower preference, whereas if the vote was not cast, the election could fail, proceed to a runoff, repeated ballot or other process, and the favored candidate could possibly win.
The Plurality system satisfies later-no-harm only because a voter is not allowed to express more than one choice.
[edit] Noncomplying methods
Approval voting, Borda count, Range voting, Schulze method and Bucklin voting do not satisfy later-no-harm. The Condorcet criterion is incompatible with later-no-harm.
When Plurality is being used to fill two or more seats in a single district (Plurality-at-large) it fails later-no-harm.
[edit] Examples
[edit] Approval voting
For example in an election using Approval voting 520 voters prefer candidates in the order A>B>C and approve only candidate A. 380 voters prefer candidates in the order B>C>A and approve only candidate B. 100 voters prefer candidates in the order C>B>A and approve candidates C and B.
A 520 | B 480 | C 100 |
A is the most approved candidate and therefore the winner.
Suppose 50 of the A>B>C voters approve both candidates A and B instead of just candidate A. The result is now:
A 520 | B 530 | C 100 |
B is now the most approved candidate and therefore the winner.
By approving an additional less preferred candidate the 50 AB voters have caused their favourite candidate to lose.
[edit] Condorcet compliant methods
For example in an election conducted using the Condorcet compliant method Ranked pairs the following votes are cast:
49: A | 25: B | 26: C>B |
B is preferred to A by 51 votes to 49 votes. A is preferred to C by 49 votes to 26 votes. C is preferred to B by 26 votes to 25 votes.
There is no Condorcet winner and B is the Ranked pairs winner.
Suppose the 25 B voters give an additional preference to their second choice C.
The votes are now:
49: A | 25: B>C | 26: C>B |
C is preferred to A by 51 votes to 49 votes. C is preferred to B by 26 votes to 25 votes. B is preferred to A by 51 votes to 49 votes.
C is now the Condorcet winner and therefore the Ranked pairs winner.
By giving a second preference to candidate C the 25 B voters have caused their first choice to be defeated.
[edit] Effect of majority requirement
In a Single transferable vote election with majority required, and full ranking is not required, the votes are as follows (for simplicity, all voters plump for their favorites):
40: A | 39: B | 21: C |
If this majority failure results in a runoff between A and B, B could win.
However, suppose the B voters decide to add a second preference for A:
40: A | 39: B>A | 21: C |
In the Preferential voting method described as an example in Robert's Rules of Order, elimination continues iteratively until "one pile contains more than half the ballots." So C would be eliminated, then B, and the B ballots would be counted for A, who would thereby obtain a majority and be elected. (If no candidate gains a majority, this will "require the voting to be repeated.") By adding a second preference vote for A, the B voters eliminated the election possibility for B.
[edit] Commentary
Woodall writes about Later-no-harm, "... under STV the later preferences on a ballot are not even considered until the fates of all candidates of earlier preference have been decided. Thus a voter can be certain that adding extra preferences to his or her preference listing can neither help nor harm any candidate already listed. Supporters of STV usually regard this as a very important property, although it has to be said that not everyone agrees; the property has been described (by Michael Dummett, in a letter to Robert Newland) as 'quite unreasonable', and (by an anonymous referee) as 'unpalatable.'"
[edit] References
- D R Woodall, "Properties of Preferential Election Rules", Voting Matters, Issue 3, December 1994 [1]
- Tony Anderson Solgard and Paul Landskroener, Bench and Bar of Minnesota, Vol 59, No 9, October 2002. [2]
- Brown v. Smallwood, 1915