Géraud de Cordemoy

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Géraud de Cordemoy, (October 6, 1626 in Paris - October 15, 1684 in Paris) a French philosopher, historian and lawyer. He is mainly known for his works in metaphysics and for his theory of language.

Portrait of Géraud de Cordemoy in the 1704 edition of the complete works
Portrait of Géraud de Cordemoy in the 1704 edition of the complete works

Contents

[edit] A short life guide

Géraud de Cordemoy was born in a family of ancient nobility coming from Auvergne (from the town of Royat). His father was a master in arts at Paris university. As for Géraud, he was a private tutor and a linguist and practised as a lawyer. Géraud de Cordemoy used to haunt the philosophical circles of the capital; he made acquaintance with Emmanuel Maignan[1] and Jacques Rohault[2]. A friend and a protégé of Bossuet who admired Descartes too, Géraud de Cordemoy was appointed reader of the Dauphin son of King Louis XIV, at the same time as Fléchier. He was elected a member of Académie française in 1675.

[edit] His works

Cordemoy is first known for having rethought the cartesian theory of causality, thus introducing the notion of “occasional cause” within a system of thought which remains essentially cartesian. He is, alongside with Arnold Geulincx and Louis de Laforge, the founder of what is called “occasionalism”. Body and soul are distinct by essence, their combination is occasional, and it is God who allows that the will to move my arm, for example, is translated into a movement. My will is an occasional cause of the movement of my arm, God is the real cause of it. What is true for the body-an individual constituted by the distinct combination of body and soul- is true for every body in the universe. God is the real and universal cause of every movement. By body, Cordemoy means the ultimate components of matter. Using a judicial figure of speech, he shows that the body, in law a person, in physics an ultimate component of matter, is indivisible. Never mentioning atomism, with that theory he comes close to the followers of Gassendi and to the free thinkers, the so called Libertines (the french Libertins]). In his work “ Le discernement du corps et de l’âme” ( discrimination between body and soul) he develops such thoughts which were criticized at that time by the followers of Descartes. In his work “ le Discours physique de la parole” (the physical Speech of the word), he asks himself the following question : how I, as a thinking being, can be certain that the human beings who surround me are also thinking beings, and not simple automatons. The problem is considered at the end of the sixth speech on discrimination between body and soul. It is the word as a vehicle of the thought which will enable me to know the existence of other individuals who are endowed with a soul like me. In a more original way, in his work “Traité physique de la parole”( physical treatise of the word)- a variation of the previous title - he develops the notion that no motivated relation between the material sign and the expressed idea exists, as much as no real relation exists between body and soul. The word represents the opportunity for sign and meaning to meet, so far as if the soul hadn’t the use of the articulated body to produce sign, it would communicate in a much more immediate way from soul to soul, without having to go through the institution of the sign. The language used by human beings is therefore too complex to be explained by purely mechanical causes; I can deduce from it that the bodies I can see are also endowed with a soul. Animals may utter sounds and parrots may reproduce words, only human beings are able to communicate ideas, and that shows the presence of a rational soul. This rational soul is able to communicate directly with angels without going through the physical articulation of the sign. “ Le Discours physique de la parole” (The physical Speech of the word), from which Molière draw the scene of the spelling lesson in “Le Bourgeois gentilhomme”, remains the most successful work of Cordemoy. American linguists such as Boas and Noam Chomsky have rediscovered him during the sixties. Cordemoy has also been known for his “Histoire de France” on which he worked for 18 years without ever seeing the end of it, so big were the contradictions he came up against while consulting the works of his predecessors. The work will finally be achieved by his elder son, Louis-Géraud de Cordemoy, and published after his death. Voltaire said about the work of Cordemoy as a historian : “ He has been the first one to be able to disentangle the chaos of the two first races of the kings of France; thanks to the duke of Montausier who charged Cordemoy with the writing of the history of Charlemagne in view of the education of Monseigneur, that useful work was achieved. He found in ancient authors nothing but absurdities and contradictions. That very difficulty encouraged him, and enabled him to disentangle the two first races”.

[edit] Publications

1691 edition of the political and historical works of Géraud de Cordemoy
1691 edition of the political and historical works of Géraud de Cordemoy

• Discours de l’action des corps (1664)

• Traité de l'esprit de l'homme et de ses facultez et fonctions, et de son union avec le corps. Suivant les principes de René Descartes (1666)

• Le discernement du corps et de l'âme, en six discours, pour servir à l'éclaircissement de la physique (1666). Texte en ligne : 1

• Discours physique de la parole (1668). Texte en ligne : 2

• Copie d'une lettre écrite à un sçavant religieux de la Compagnie de Jésus, pour montrer : I, que le système de M. Descartes et son opinion touchant les bestes n'ont rien de dangereux ; II, et que tout ce qu'il en a écrit semble estre tiré du premier chapitre de la Genèse (1668). Texte en ligne : 3

• Lettre d'un philosophe à un cartesien de ses amis (1672)

• Discours sur la pureté de l'esprit et du corps et par occasion de la vie innocente et juste des premiers Chrétiens (1677)

• Histoire de France, depuis le temps des Gaulois et le commencement de la monarchie, jusqu'en 987 (2 volumes, 1687-89). Complétée et publiée par son fils, Louis-Géraud de Cordemoy.

• Dissertations physiques sur le discernement du corps et de l'âme, sur la parole, et sur le système de M. Descartes (1689-90)

• Divers traitez de métaphysique, d'histoire et de politique (1691). Texte en ligne : 4

• Les Œuvres de feu monsieur de Cordemoy (1704). Publiées par son fils, Louis-Géraud de Cordemoy. Contiennent : Six discours sur la distinction et l'union des corps ; Discours physique sur la Parole ; Lettre sur la conformité du système de Descartes avec le premier chapitre de la Genèse ; Deux petits traités de métaphysique ; Divers petits traités sur l'histoire et sur la métaphysique ; Divers petits traités sur l'histoire et sur la politique.

• Gérauld de Cordemoy (1626-1684). Œuvres philosophiques. Avec une étude bio-bibliographique, Presses Universitaires de France, Paris, 1968

[edit] Bibliography

Ablondi, (Fred.), Gerauld de Cordemoy: Atomist, Occasionalist, Cartesian, Milwaukee, Marquette University Press, 2005.

Balz (A. G. A.), Cartesian studies, chapitre Géraud de Cordemoy : pp. 3 à 27, New-York, 1951.

Battail (Jean-François), L’Avocat philosophe Géraud de Cordemoy, (1626-1684), Martinus Nijhoff, La Haye, 1973.

Boas (George), « Cordemoy and Malebranche »( in Dominant theme of modern philosophy, A history) New York, 1957.

Brun (Jean), article « Cordemoy », in Dictionnaire du Grand Siècle ..., Paris, 1990, p.407-408.

Chomsky (Noam), Cartesian linguistics: a chapter in the history of rationalist thought. New York: Harper & Row, 1966. La Linguistique cartésienne, Editions du Seuil, 1969. - « De quelques constantes en théorie linguistique » Revue Diogène, Paris, 1965.

Clair (Pierre) et Girbal (François), Oeuvres philosophiques de Géraud de Cordemoy, avec une Etude bio-bibliographique, Edition critique, sixième volume de la collection «Le mouvement des idées au XVIIe siècle» (dirigée par André Robinet), Paris, P.U.F., 1968.

Clavier (Paul-Henri), Géraud de Cordemoy : historien, politique et pédagogue, Thèse de doctorat soutenue en juillet 2006, Université Marc Bloch, Strasbourg.

Cuche (François-Xavier), « Le Petit Concile et la Ville – essai sur la politique de la ville chez Bossuet et son entourage », in Pouvoirs, Ville, Société, Paris, 1983, pp.279-289.

Deprun (Jean), « Cordemoy et la réforme de l’enseignement », in Le XVIle siècle et l'éducation, supplément au n°88 de la revue Marseille, 1972, 1er trimestre, pp.41-43.

Guerrini (Luigi), Occasinalismo e teoria della communicazione in Gerauld de Cordemoy, Annali di dipartimento di filosofia, IX, 1993 (1994), 63 – 80.

Nadler (Steven), « Cordemoy and Occasionalism », Journal of the History of Philosophy 43: 37-54, 2005.

Nicolosi (Salvatore), Il Dualismo da Cartesio a Leibniz (Cartesio, Cordemoy, La Forge, Malebranche, Leibniz), Marsilio Editori S.P.A. in Venezia, 1987.

Scheib (Andreas), Zur Theorie individueller Substanzen bei Géraud de Cordemoy, P. Lang, Frankfurt am Main, New York, 1997.

Thuillier (Guy), « Une utopie au grand siècle : De la réformation d’un Etat de Géraud de Cordemoy, 1668 » in Revue administrative, pp. 257 à 262, vol.75, mai-juin 1960.


[edit] External links