Fatou's lemma
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
In mathematics, Fatou's lemma establishes an inequality relating the integral (in the sense of Lebesgue) of the limit inferior of a sequence of functions to the limit inferior of integrals of these functions. The lemma is named after the French mathematician Pierre Fatou (1878 - 1929).
Fatou's lemma can be used to prove the Fatou–Lebesgue theorem and Lebesgue's dominated convergence theorem.
Contents |
[edit] Standard statement of Fatou's lemma
If f1, f2, . . . is a sequence of non-negative measurable functions defined on a measure space (S,Σ,μ), then
Note: On the left-hand side the limit inferior of the fn is taken pointwise. The functions are allowed to attain the value infinity and the integrals may also be infinite.
[edit] Proof
Fatou's lemma is here proved using the monotone convergence theorem (it can be proved directly).
Let f denote the limit inferior of the fn. For every natural number k define pointwise the function
Then the sequence g1, g2, . . . is increasing and converges pointwise to f. For k ≤ n, we have gk ≤ fn, so that
hence
Using the monotone convergence theorem, the last inequality, and the definition of the limit inferior, it follows that
[edit] Examples for strict inequality
Equip the space S with the Borel σ-algebra and the Lebesgue measure.
- Example for a probability space: Let S = [0,1] denote the unit interval. For every natural number n define
- Example with uniform convergence: Let S denote the set of all real numbers. Define
These sequences converge on S pointwise (respectively uniform) to the zero function (with zero integral), but every fn has integral one.
[edit] Reverse Fatou lemma
Let f1, f2, . . . be a sequence of extended real-valued measurable functions defined on a measure space (S,Σ,μ). If there exists a non-negative integrable function g on S such that fn ≤ g for all n, then
Note: Here g integrable means that g is measurable and that .
[edit] Proof
Apply Fatou's lemma to the non-negative sequence given by g – fn.
[edit] Extensions and variations of Fatou's lemma
[edit] Integrable lower bound
Let f1, f2, . . . be a sequence of extended real-valued measurable functions defined on a measure space (S,Σ,μ). If there exists a non-negative integrable function g on S such that fn ≥ −g for all n, then
[edit] Proof
Apply Fatou's lemma to the non-negative sequence given by fn + g.
[edit] Pointwise convergence
If in the previous setting the sequence f1, f2, . . . converges pointwise to a function f μ-almost everywhere on S, then
[edit] Proof
Note that f has to agree with the limit inferior of the functions fn almost everywhere, and that the values of the integrand on a set of measure zero have no influence on the value of the integral.
[edit] Convergence in measure
The last assertion also holds, if the sequence f1, f2, . . . converges in measure to a function f.
[edit] Proof
There exists a subsequence such that
Since this subsequence also converges in measure to f, there exists a further subsequence, which converges pointwise to f almost everywhere, hence the previous variation of Fatou's lemma is applicable to this subsubsequence.
[edit] Fatou's lemma for conditional expectations
In probability theory, by a change of notation, the above versions of Fatou's lemma are applicable to sequences of random variables X1, X2, . . . defined on a probability space ; the integrals turn into expectations. In addition, there is also a version for conditional expectations:
Let X1, X2, . . . be a sequence of non-negative random variables on a probability space and let be a sub-σ-algebra. Then
Note: Conditional expectation for non-negative random variables is always well defined, finite expectation is not needed.
[edit] Proof
Besides a change of notation, the proof is very similar to the one for the standard version of Fatou's lemma above, however the monotone convergence theorem for conditional expectations has to be applied.
Let X denote the limit inferior of the Xn. For every natural number k define pointwise the random variable
Then the sequence Y1, Y2, . . . is increasing and converges pointwise to X. For k ≤ n, we have Yk ≤ Xn, so that
- almost surely
by the monotonicity of conditional expectation, hence
- almost surely,
because the countable union of the exceptional sets of probability zero is again a null set. Using the definition of X, its representation as pointwise limit of the Yk, the monotone convergence theorem for conditional expectations, the last inequality, and the definition of the limit inferior, it follows that almost surely
[edit] External links
[edit] References
- H.L. Royden, "Real Analysis", Prentice Hall, 1988.