Educational Philosophy of Martin Heidegger
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
This article or section needs to be wikified to meet Wikipedia's quality standards. Please help improve this article with relevant internal links. (June 2007) |
This section is written like a personal reflection or essay and may require cleanup. Please help improve it by rewriting it in an encyclopedic style. (December 2007) |
This article is orphaned as few or no other articles link to it. Please help introduce links in articles on related topics. (January 2008) |
There is today significant interest in Heidegger as an educational philosopher worldwide. Some reasons for this can be discerned. New Heideggerian material in English is being published; new interpretations are appearing; and there are those who seek to tease out the implications of Heideggerian thought in the practical world (Heidegger 2005; Inwood 2002b, p. ix; Skirbekk 1969; Tallis 2002; Young 2002). The new interpretation of Being and Time by Stambaugh reads differently from the Macquarrie Robinson translation from its very first sentence (Heidegger 1996). There is also a developing literature that seeks to relate Heidegger’s writing to his lived life and circumstances. This has provided new perspectives regarding the theory (Caputo 1993; Wolin 2001; Wolin 1993). In addition, the hermeneutic philosophy of science is drawing upon and developing Heidegger’s ideas (Babich 2002b; Ginev 2002; Mays 2002; Toulmin 2002).
There is a debate about the potential of Heidegger’s work to inform educational thinking and practice (Peters 2002). “Although Heidegger’s work has influenced scholarship in numerous fields, little to no influence has found its way into education” (Ream & Ream 2005, p. 589).
Heidegger might initially appear to be a strange candidate for the role of educational reformer because he was as an author said “ultraconservative” and was fond of repeating Hölderlin’s maxim “As you begin, so you shall remain” ({{Harvnb|Wolin|2001|p=207 206). Gur-Ze’ev notes “… Heidegger makes no effort to contribute to normalizing education or to scientific thinking … nor can he contribute, as some scholars would suggest, to the improvement of schooling” (Gur-Ze'ev 2002, p. 75). T. E. Peterson (Peterson 2005) writes about Heidegger’s authoritarian pedagogy, his autocratic approach to university administration, and the relationship of these things to Weimar Germany.
Cooper argues that Heidegger’s philosophy as a whole can assist our understanding of education. He says that educationalists should be helpfully informed by Heidegger’s “way of looking at the world” and his philosophy as a whole, both as a perspective in itself and also because of the more full understanding of specific ideas that such a perspective may bring (Cooper 2002, p. 47). Cooper focuses on the nature of truth and the status of science, which are relevant to schooling. Hogan elaborates on where to find the potential of Heidegger to inform education. For him it is in Heidegger’s difference from “what the dominant modes and tempers in Western philosophy have furnished for thought and action” (Hogan 2002, p. 211).
There are intellectual disciplines and sectors of education where people have sought to make use of Heidegger’s work. Cooper cites examples of Heidegger’s thought in several disciplines, Lambeir considers information technology in schools, and Thomson considers how Heidegger might provide a “positive vision for the future of higher education” by understanding our educational crisis “ontohistorically” (Cooper 2002, p. 47; Lambeir 2002; Thomson 2001). Gur-Ze’ev suggests that the “philosophy of Martin Heidegger is of much relevance for the elaboration of an attempt to open the gate to counter-education as an open possibility” (Gur-Ze'ev & 2002 p.67). Bonnett explores how Heidegger contributes to our understanding of learning and a “full educational relationship between learner and teacher” (Bonnett 2002, p. 230). Bonnett and Morris have attempted to speak directly to teachers about the use of existentialism in practice (Bonnett 1994; Morris 1961; Morris 1966).
There are also papers that take some aspect of Heidegger and relate that to some disciplinary area of education. Examples are relatively common in nursing education (Diekelmann & Ironside 1998; Van Der Wal 2001), and there is Irwin’s paper on Heidegger and Nietzsche in relation to values education (Irwin 2003). There are also specifically curriculum oriented papers, for example there is one that uses Heidegger’s work to draw conclusions about the teaching of English (Pike 2003) and I have developed a science distance education pedagogy drawing on Heidegger (Shaw 2004). Greene has related the teaching of literature to Merleau-Ponty, Camus and Heidegger (Greene 1997). By reading Moby Dick, she says, students can gain self-understanding through the experience of having things revealed or unconcealed. She cites Poetry Language and Thought as supportive of this view (Greene 1997, p. 172 173). All these papers make use of things Heidegger wrote and probably gain authority from the citation. However, they do not strongly relate curriculum or subject areas to the core of Heidegger’s work. They do not take being/truth and link that whole phenomenon to their curriculum interest. Perhaps those who write about Heidegger and the arts curriculum (widely interpreted) are the exception to this generalisation.
The latter Heidegger wrote a great deal about art, and he related this to truth and being in a direct way (Babich 2002a). Consequently, those concerned with the arts in education were led naturally to consider what I have called the “core” of Heidegger’s thesis. One example is the work of Mansfield in the field of music education. She cites evidence of the extent to which music education is defined by an implicit but little understood ground of Enframing (Gestell), relates a music curriculum directly to the value of technology, and relates being and disclosure to art (J. Mansfield 2005; J. E. Mansfield 2003). Grierson has also provided an account of art, technology and a close reading of Heidegger (Grierson 2003).
The core of Heidegger’s work is his concern with Being which he describes as the “matter of thinking” (Young 2002, p. 5) and Being constitutes the “hidden essence of truth” (Heidegger 1969, p. 83). Whilst there is interest in Heidegger’s work in relation to education, there does not appear to be much on the very critical matter of truth and its direct involvement in thinking about education. No one seems to have asked how Heidegger’s ontological concept of truth might be of use in our engagement with contemporary pedagogical concerns.
I have suggested that recent debates in education that draw upon Heidegger are not closely associated with Heideggerian being/truth. As recent commentators said “… further work needs to be done in order to demonstrate the relationship shared by Heidegger’s theory of ontology and learning environments” (Ream & Ream 2005, p. 589).
However, there is some work by “existential phenomenologists” (the term Donald Vandenberg uses to describe himself) that may be heading towards the Heideggerian core. Vandenberg brought into English the work of Continental writers who are concerned with schooling and phenomenology.
Because of their potential relevance to thinking about the development of horizons of disclosure, I want to record two of the contributions by the existentialist phenomenologists: the “being-in-the-law” idea and the existential model of human development.
The idea of “being-in-the-law” is an extension of Heidegger’s terminology into a practical and intellectual discipline. It heralds a discussion about a new horizon. Vandenberg sets out the base concept clearly: “The designation being-in-the-law concerns the externalization of one’s projection in accordance to the space of law in the generic sense, which means into the space disclosed by particular laws that are absolutely just, but to none other” (Vandenberg 1971, p. 200).
“That is, laws do not exist in books, courts or out in social space: they become grounded ontologically only in individual existence through the individual’s projection into the space they define. … He who does not see that the laws are to be ‘obeyed’ needs not legal instruction but an existential conversion from being-in-the-world to being-in-the-law that is not unlike the conversion from being-in-the-world to being in the truth” (Vandenberg 1971, p. 201 202, who acknowledged his debt to Maihofer).
Kierkegaard and Gardini hypothesis existential “life-phases” based upon events such as conception, birth, pubescence, societal entrance, levelling off, retirement, and dependence. Kierkegaard’s phases are the:
- Esthetic phase (resolution of crises of experience)
- Ethical phase (idealism, hedonistic resolution)
- Teleological phase (synthesis of the earlier phases).
Gardini’s life phases are:
- Pre natal life
- Childhood
- Youth
- Young adulthood
- Mature adulthood
- Old age
- Senility.
Gardini’s life phases—which, he says, are not clearly separate one from the other in practice—are hypothesised as “ontologically distinct forms of existence”. In this way, he introduces the possibility of developing the concept of Dasein and the possibility of relating horizons (and thus truth) to Dasein in a more comprehensive manner. We might consider the Child-Dasein, Dasein, and Elderly-Dasein, each with different forms or ways of being.
One purpose of Vandenberg’s book Being and Education is to develop a phenomenological account of the development of Dasein through stages (Vandenberg 1971). Examining stage theories is beyond the scope of the present theses, however the ideas that they relate to are of interest because the notion of pedagogy involves change in the student and we may discover something helpful if we consider ontological and phenomenological accounts of Dasein that relate to change.
My conclusion about Heidegger and education generally is that there is extensive interest in his work and its potential to inform education. However, there is little focus on how the core of Heidegger’s thinking, which is the being/truth concept (that entails the notion of horizon). It is this concept that might be the base of a systematic pedagogy. Some scholars have produced works relevant to aspects of this theme, including the educational phenomenologists. However, I have been unable to identify anyone who has directly addressed the question of Heideggerian truth and pedagogy.
[edit] Bibliography
- Adorno, T. W., written at Evanston, IL, The jargon of authenticity, Northwestern University Press.
Aristotle. (1990). Nicomachean ethics (D. W. Ross, Trans.). In The works of Aristotle (2nd ed., Vol. II, pp. 339-444). Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica.
Babich, B. E. (2002a). Heidegger's truth of art and the question of aesthetics. In B. E. Babich (Ed.), Hermeneutic philosophy of science, Van Gogh's eyes, and God: essays in honor of Patrick A. Heelan (pp. 265-263). Dordrecht-Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Babich, B. E. (Ed.). (2002b). Hermeneutic philosophy of science, Van Gogh's eyes, and God: essays in honor of Patrick A. Heelan. Dordrecht-Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Bohman, J. (2005). Critical Theory. Retrieved 23 March, 2005, from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2005/entries/critical-theory/
Bonnett, M. (1994). Children's thinking: promoting understanding in the primary school. New York, NY: Cassell Education.
Bonnett, M. (2002). Education as a form of the poetic: a Heideggerian approach to learning and the teacher-pupil relationship. In M. A. Peters (Ed.), Heidegger, education, and modernity (pp. 229-243). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
Campbell, R. (1992). Truth and historicity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Campbell, R. (1992). Truth and historicity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Caputo, J. D., Demythologizing Heidegger, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Cooper, D. E. (2002). Truth, science, thinking, and distress. In M. A. Peters (Ed.), Heidegger, education, and modernity (pp. 47-63). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers Ltd.
Dahlstrom, D. O. (2001). Heidegger's concept of truth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Diekelmann, N. & Ironside, P. M., “Preserving writing in doctoral education: exploring the concernful practices of schooling learning teaching”, Journal of Advanced Nursing 28 (6): 1347-1356
Dreyfus, H. L. (1991). Being-in-the-World: a commentary on Heidegger's "Being and Time", Division 1. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Dreyfus, H. L. (2000). How Heidegger defends the possibility of a correspondence theory of truth with respect to the entities of natural science. In T. R. Schatzki, K. K. Cetina & E. von Savigny (Eds.), The practice turn in contemporary theory (pp. 151-162). New York: Routledge.
Engels-Schwarzpaul, A. (2003). Ways of appropriating: culture as resource and standing reserve. Access: Critical Perspectives on Communication, Cultural and Policy Studies, 22(1/2), 35-45.
Fjelland, R. (2002). The 'Copenhagen Interpretation' of quantum mechanics and phenomenology. In B. E. Babich (Ed.), Hermeneutic philosophy of science, Van Gogh's eyes, and God: essays in honor of Patrick A. Heelan (pp. 53-65). Dordrecht-Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Ginev, D. (2002). The hermeneutic context of constitution. In B. E. Babich (Ed.), Hermeneutic philosophy of science, Van Gogh's eyes, and God: essays in honor of Patrick A. Heelan (pp. 43-52). Dordrecht ; Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Giroux, H. A. (1997). Pedagogy and the politics of hope: theory, culture, and schooling: a critical reader. Boulder: WestviewPress.
Gogel, R. E. (1987). Quest for measure: the phenomenological problem of truth. New York: P. Lang.
Greene, M. (1997). The lived world, literature, and education. In D. Vandenberg (Ed.), Phenomenology and educational discourse (pp. 169-190). Johannesburg: Heinemann.
Grierson, E. M. (2003). Heeding Heidegger's way: questions of the work of art. Access: Critical Perspectives on Communication, Cultural and Policy Studies, 22(1/2), 23-33.
Groth, M. (1997). Heidegger's Philosophy of Translation. Unpublished Ph.D., Fordham University, New York.
Gur-Ze'ev, I. (2002). Martin Heidegger, Transcendence, and the Possibility of Counter-Education. In M. A. Peters (Ed.), Heidegger, education, and modernity (pp. 65-80). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers Ltd.
Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.
Heidegger, M. (1969). Discourse on thinking: A translation of Gelassenheit (J. M. Anderson & E. H. Freund, Trans.). New York: Harper & Row.
Heidegger, M. (1972). On time and being (J. Stambaugh, Trans.). New York: Harper & Row.
Heidegger, M. (1982). The basic problems of phenomenology (A. Hofstadter, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, M. (1984). The metaphysical foundations of logic. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, M. (1993). Basic writings: from Being and time (1927) to The task of thinking (1964) (D. F. Krell, Trans.). New York: Harper Collins.
Heidegger, M. (1996). Being and time: a translation of Sein und Zeit (J. Stambaugh, Trans.). Albany: State University of New York Press.
Heidegger, M. (1998). Pathmarks (W. McNeill, Trans.). Cambridge-New York: Cambridge University Press.
Heidegger, M. (1999). Ontology - the hermeneutics of facticity (J. van Buren, Trans.). Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, M. (2001). Phenomenological interpretations of Aristotle: initiation into phenomenological research (R. Rojcewicz, Trans.). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, M. (2005). Introduction to phenomenological research (D. O. Dahlstrom, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Hirst, P. H. (1972). Liberal education and the nature of knowledge. In R. F. Dearden, P. H. Hirst & R. S. Peters (Eds.), Education and the development of reason (Vol. 3, pp. 1-24). London-Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Hogan, P. (2002). Learning as leavetaking and homecoming. In M. A. Peters (Ed.), Heidegger, education, and modernity (pp. 211-228). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers Ltd.
Ihde, D. (1974). Phenomenology and the later Heidegger. Philosophy Today, 18, 19-31.
Ihde, D. (1997, 15 November 1997). Expanding hermeneutics. Retrieved 12 January 2003, from http://ws.cc.stonybrook.edu/philosophy/faculty/papers/Expherm.htm
Inwood, M. (1997). Heidegger. Oxford-New York: Oxford University Press.
Inwood, M. (2000). Heidegger: a very short introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Inwood, M. (2002a). Disclosing the world: Book Review: Heidegger's Concept of Truth by Daniel Dahlstrom. Times Literary Supplement, 3 May 2002, p. 27.
Inwood, M. (2002b). Speak to me, chair: Book Review: A conversation with Martin Heidegger, by Raymond Tallis. Times Higher Education Supplement, 25 October 2002, p. 28.
Irwin, R. (2003). Heidegger and Nietzsche: The Question of Value and Nihilism in Relation to Education. Studies in Philosophy & Education, 22(3/4), 227-245.
Kant, I. (1996). Critique of pure reason: With all variants from the 1781 and 1787 editions (W. S. Pluhar, Trans.). Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett Publishing.
Kisiel, T. J. (1993). The genesis of Heidegger's Being and Time. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Lambeir, B. (2002). Comfortably numb in the digital era: Man's being as standing-reserve or dwelling silently. In M. A. Peters (Ed.), Heidegger, education, and modernity (pp. 103-121). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.
Lynch, M. P. (Ed.). (2001). The nature of truth: classic and contemporary perspectives. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.
Mansfield, J. (2005). The global musical subject, curriculum and Heidegger's questioning concerning technology. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 37(1), 133-148.
Mansfield, J. E. (2003). Framing the musical subject, technoculture and curriculum: a Heideggerian critique. Access: Critical Perspectives on Communication, Cultural and Policy Studies, 22(1/2), 55-65.
Marcuse, H. (1991). One-dimensional man: studies in the ideology of advanced industrial society. London: Routledge.
Marx, W. (1971). Heidegger and the tradition (T. Kisiel & M. Greene, Trans.). Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press.
Mays, W. (2002). Piaget and Husserl: on theory and praxis in science. In B. E. Babich (Ed.), Hermeneutic philosophy of science, Van Gogh's eyes, and God: essays in honor of Patrick A. Heelan (pp. 177-185). Dordrecht ; Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Morris, V. C. (1961). Philosophy and the American school: an introduction to the philosophy of education. Cambridge, MA: The Riverside Press.
Morris, V. C. (1966). Existentialism in education: what it means. New York: Harper & Row.
Oxford English Dictionary. (2000-). OED Online: Oxford University Press.
Parry, R. (2003). Episteme and Techne. Retrieved 23 June 2005, 2005, from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2003/entries/episteme-techne/
Peters, M. (Ed.). (2002). Heidegger, education, and modernity. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Peterson, T. E. (2005). Notes on Heidegger's authoritarian pedagogy. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 37(4), 599-623.
Philipse, H. (1998). Heidegger's philosophy of being: a critical interpretation. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
Philipse, H. (2001). What is a natural conception of the world? International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 9(3), 385-399.
Pike, M. A. (2003). On Being in English teaching: a time for Heidegger? Changing English: Studies in Reading & Culture, 10(1), 91-100.
Ream, T. C., & Ream, T. W. (2005). From Low-Lying Roofs to Towering Spires: Toward a Heideggerian understanding of learning environments. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 37(4), 585-597.
Shaw, R. (2004). The Black Hole Theory of Teaching: the future of assessment and course delivery in New Zealand secondary schools. Paper presented at the New Zealand Post Primary Teachers' Association Conference: Charting the Future, Wellington, 18-20 April 2004.
Skirbekk, G. (1969). Truth and preconditions: an interpretation of Heidegger's theory of truth. Unpublished PhD, Universitetet i Bergen, Bergen.
Tallis, R. (2002). A conversation with Martin Heidegger. New York: Palgrave.
Taylor, L. G. (1990). The centrality of "The Horizon" in Husserl and Heidegger. Contemporary Philosophy, May-June 1990, 19-23.
Thomas, V. C. (1990). The Development of Time Consciousness from Husserl to Heidegger. In A.-T. Tymieniecka (Ed.), Analecta Husserliana, XXXI. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- Thomson, I., “Heidegger on ontological education, or: How we become what we are”, Inquiry 44 (3): 243-268
- Toulmin, S., “The hermeneutics of the natural sciences”, in Babich, B. E., Hermeneutic philosophy of science, Van Gogh's eyes, and God: essays in honor of Patrick A. Heelan, Dordrecht-Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 25-29.
- Vandenberg, D., Being and education: an essay in existential phenomenology, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
- Warren, J. W., Understanding force: an account of some aspects of teaching the idea of force in school, college and university courses in engineering, mathematics and science, London: J. Murray.
- Weatherston, M., written at University of Toronto, Toronto, Canada, Categories and temporality: Heidegger's interpretation of Kant, Unpublished Ph.D. (Philosophy), <http://www.esu.edu/phil/mwthesis/ct-pref.html>. Retrieved on 28 January 2008.
- Wolin, R., Heidegger's children: Hannah Arendt, Karl Löwith, Hans Jonas, and Herbert Marcuse, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
- Wolin, R.(Ed.), The Heidegger controversy: a critical reader, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Wrathall, M. A., “Heidegger and Truth as Correspondence”, International Journal of Philosophical Studies 7 (1): 69-88.
- Young, J., Heidegger's philosophy of art, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Young, J., Heidegger's later philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.