Unifying theories in mathematics
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
There have been several attempts in history to reach a unified theory of mathematics. Some of the greatest mathematicians have expressed that the whole subject should be fitted into one theory.
[edit] Historical perspective
This (often informal) process might be seen as helping to define what constitutes mathematics. For example, mechanics and mathematical analysis were commonly combined into one subject during the 18th century, united by the differential equation concept; while algebra and geometry were considered largely distinct. Now we consider analysis, algebra, and geometry, but not mechanics, as parts of mathematics because they are primarily deductive sciences, while mechanics like physics must proceed from observation. There is no major loss of content, with analytical mechanics in the old sense now expressed in terms of symplectic topology, based on the newer theory of manifolds.
[edit] Mathematical theories
The term theory is used informally within mathematics to mean a self-consistent body of definitions, axioms, theorems, examples, and so on. (Examples include group theory, Galois theory, control theory, and K-theory.) In particular there is no connotation of hypothetical. Thus the term unifying theory is more like a sociological term used to study the actions of mathematicians. It may assume nothing conjectural, that would be analogous to an undiscovered scientific link. There is really no cognate within mathematics to such concepts as Proto-World in linguistics or the Gaia hypothesis.
Nonetheless there have been several episodes within the history of mathematics in which sets of individual theorems were found to be special cases of a single unifying result, or in which a single perspective about how to proceed when developing an area of mathematics could be applied fruitfully to multiple branches of the subject.
[edit] Geometrical theories
A well-known example was the development of analytic geometry, which in the hands of mathematicians such as Descartes and Fermat showed that many theorems about curves and surfaces of special types could be stated in algebraic language (then new), each of which could then be proved using the same techniques (that is, the theorems were very similar algebraically, even if the geometrical interpretations were distinct.)
At the end of the 19th century, Felix Klein noted that the many branches of geometry which had been developed during that century (affine geometry, projective geometry, hyperbolic geometry, etc.) could all be treated in a uniform way by considering the groups under which the objects were invariant (the Erlangen programme).
[edit] Through-axiomatisation
Early in the 20th century, parallel to the development of mathematical logic as a stand-alone branch of mathematics, many parts of mathematics began to be treated by delineating useful sets of axioms and then studying their consequences. Thus, for example, the studies of "hypercomplex numbers", popular at the turn of the century, were put onto an axiomatic footing as branches of ring theory (in this case, specifically meaning associative algebras over the field of complex numbers.)
In most cases, the objects under study can be defined as sets (or more informally, as sets with additional structure such as an addition operation). Set theory serves as a lingua franca for the development of mathematical themes.
[edit] Bourbaki
The cause of axiomatic development was taken up in earnest by the Bourbaki group of mathematicians. Taken to its extreme this attitude demanded developing mathematics in its greatest generality, starting from the most general axioms and then specializing (e.g. introducing modules over commutative rings and limiting to vector spaces over the real numbers only when absolutely necessary) even when the specializations were the theorems of primary interest.
In particular, this perspective placed little value on fields of mathematics (such as combinatorics) whose objects of study are very often special, or found in situations which can only superficially be related to more axiomatic branches of the subject.
[edit] Category theory as a rival
An alternative (mostly complementary) to set theory but also serving to give a consistent approach to most of axiomatic mathematics is category theory, developed in the second half of the 20th century. A key theme from this point of view is that mathematics studies not only of certain kinds of objects (Lie groups, Banach spaces, etc.) but also of the mappings between them.
In particular, this clarifies exactly what it means for the mathematical objects to be considered to be the same. (For example, are all equilateral triangles the same, or does size matter?) Saunders Mac Lane proposed that any concept with enough 'ubiquity' (occurring in various branches of mathematics) deserved isolating and studying in its own right. Category theory is better adapted to that end, than any other current approach. The disadvantages of relying on so-called abstract nonsense are a certain blandness, and abstraction in the sense of breaking away from the roots in concrete problems. Nevertheless the methods of category theory have steadily advanced in acceptance, in numerous areas (from D-modules to categorical logic).
[edit] Uniting theories
On a less grandiose scale, there are frequent instances in which it appears that sets of results in two different branches of mathematics are similar, and one might ask whether there is a unifying framework which clarifies the connections. We have already noted the example of analytic geometry, and more generally the field of algebraic geometry thoroughly develops the connections between geometric objects (varieties, or more generally schemes) and algebraic ones (ideals); the touchstone result here is Hilbert's Nullstellensatz which roughly speaking shows that there is a natural one-to-one correspondence between the two types of objects.
One may view other theorems in the same light. For example the fundamental theorem of Galois theory asserts that there is a one-to-one correspondence between extensions of a field and subgroups of the field's Galois group. The Taniyama conjecture for elliptic curves (now proven) establishes a one-to-one correspondence between curves defined one way (the modular curves) and curves defined a different way (at least, over the field of rational numbers). A research area sometimes nicknamed Monstrous Moonshine developed connections between modular forms and the finite simple group known as the Monster, starting solely with the surprise observation that in each of them the rather unusual number 196884 would arise very naturally. Another field, known as the Langlands Program, likewise starts with apparently haphazard similarities (in this case, between number-theoretical results and representations of certain groups) and looks for constructions from which both sets of results would be corollaries.
[edit] Reference list of major unifying concepts
A short list of these theories might include:
- Cartesian geometry
- Calculus
- Complex analysis
- Galois theory
- Erlangen programme
- Lie group
- Set theory
- Hilbert space
- Computable function
- Characteristic classes
- Homological algebra
- Homotopy theory
- Grothendieck's schemes
- Langlands philosophy
- Non-commutative geometry.
We illustrate the concept by discussing some of these themes in detail.
[edit] Recent developments in relation with modular theory
A well-known example is the Taniyama-Shimura conjecture, now the modularity theorem, which proposed that each elliptic curve over the rational numbers can be translated into a modular form (in such a way as to preserve the associated L-function). There are difficulties in identifying this with an isomorphism, in any strict sense of the word. Certain curves had been known to be both elliptic curves (of genus 1) and modular curves, before the conjecture was formulated (about 1955). The surprising part of the conjecture was the extension to factors of Jacobians of modular curves of genus >1. It had probably not seemed plausible that there would be 'enough' such rational factors, before the conjecture was enunciated; and in fact the numerical evidence was slight until around 1970, when tables began to confirm it. The case of elliptic curves with complex multiplication was proved by Shimura in 1964. This conjecture stood for decades before being proved in generality.
In fact the Langlands philosophy is much more like a web of unifying conjectures; it really does postulate that the general theory of automorphic forms is regulated by the L-groups introduced by Robert Langlands. His principle of functoriality with respect to the L-group has a very large explanatory value with respect to known types of lifting of automorphic forms (now more broadly studied as automorphic representations). While this theory is in one sense closely linked with the Taniyama-Shimura conjecture, it should be understood that the conjecture actually operates in the opposite direction. It requires the existence of an automorphic form, starting with an object that (very abstractly) lies in a category of motives.
Another significant related point is that the Langlands approach stands apart from the whole development triggered by monstrous moonshine (connections between elliptic modular functions as Fourier series, and the group representations of the Monster group and other sporadic groups). The Langlands philosophy neither foreshadowed nor was able to include this line of research.
[edit] Isomorphism conjectures in K-theory
Another case, which so far is less well-developed but covers a wide range of mathematics, is the conjectural basis of some parts of K-theory. The Baum-Connes conjecture, now a long-standing problem, has been joined by others in a group known as the isomorphism conjectures in K-theory. These include the Farrell-Jones conjecture and Bost conjecture.