Ethical arguments regarding torture
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Ethical arguments have arisen regarding torture, and its debated value to society. Despite worldwide condemnation and the existence of treaty provisions that forbid it, some countries still use it. The ethical assertion that torture is a tool is at question.
Contents |
[edit] Premise
The basic ethical debate is a matter of deontological versus utilitarian viewpoints. The utilitarian thinker believes the ends can justify the means; the intention behind any action is held as the primary factor in determining its merit or morality. This ideology presupposes, though, the trustworthiness of the acting parties, when their best interests clearly lie in claiming what will seem a defensible motive. After the fact, one can choose the version of reality in which they look best, the justification that will earn them praise rather than penalty.
The opposite view is the deontological, which relies on objectively measurable facts and demonstrable results. A man stands before you and acknowledges that he has caused another living being great pain and injury. In the first school of thought explained above, you have the option to excuse his actions 100% if he ascribes a noble intent. Teleological evaluation would merely consider whether it was necessary that the pain was caused at all. Teleology does not care why, only what; causality is the sole measure of necessity; if the two men could have possibly gotten through the encounter without either one being injured severely, then it is clear that the aggressor was using force beyond reasonable limits.
[edit] History
Historically, torture has been reviled as an idea, yet employed as a tool and defended by its wielders, often in direct contradiction to their own averred beliefs. Judicial torture was a common feature of the legal systems of many countries including all Civil Law countries in Europe until around the French Revolution. This was part of ancient Greek and Roman Law theory that remained valid in Europe. Roman Law assumed, for example, that slaves would not tell the truth in a legal court as they were always vulnerable to threats from their owners. Their testimony could only be of value if it was extracted by a greater fear of torture. Legal scholars were well aware of the problems of false testimony produced by the threat of torture. In theory torture was not meant to produce a confession as such, but rather details of the crime or crime scene which only the guilty party would know.
In early modern times under certain conditions, torture was used in England. For example the confession of Marc Smeaton at the trial of Anne Boleyn was presented in written form only, either to hide from the court that Smeaton had been tortured on the rack for four hours, or because Thomas Cromwell was worried that he would recant his confession if cross examined. When Guy Fawkes was arrested for his role in the Gunpowder Plot of 1605 he was tortured until he revealed all he knew about the plot. This was not so much to extract a confession, which was not needed to prove his guilt, but to extract from him the names of his fellow conspirators. By this time torture was not routine in England and a special warrant from King James I was needed before he could be tortured. The wording of the warrant shows some concerns for humanitarian considerations, the severity of the methods of interrogation were to be increased gradually until the interrogators were sure that Fawkes had told all he knew. In the end this did not help Fawkes much as he was broken on the only rack in England, which was in the Tower of London. Torture was abolished in England around 1640 (except peine forte et dure which was abolished in 1772).
The use of torture in Europe came under attack during the Enlightenment. Cesare Beccaria's On Crimes and Punishments (1764) denounced the use of torture as cruel and contrary to reason. The French Revolution abolished the use of torture in France and the French Armies carried abolition to most of the rest of Europe. The last European jurisdictions to abolish legal torture were Portugal (1828) and the canton of Glarus in Switzerland (1848). As long as torture was used within reasonable limits, it did not present grave moral obstacles to the majority of pre-modern European thinkers.[citation needed]
Under codified legal systems such as France, torture was superseded with a legal system that is highly dependent on investigating magistrates and the confession remains The Queen of Proofs. Such magistrates are often under pressure to produce results. It is alleged that in many cases police violence towards suspects has been ignored by the magistrates. In the adversarial system of Common Law used throughout the English speaking world, the experience is a different one. As the two parties have to convince a jury whether the defendant in a case is guilty or innocent of a crime, if the defence can persuade a jury that reasonable doubt exists over the credibility of a confession then the jury is likely to disregard the confession. If the defence can show that the confession was made under such duress that most people would make such a confession, then the jury is likely to question the confessions credibility. Usually the more duress that can be shown to have been used by law enforcement by the defence, the less weight most juries will place on confessions. In Britain partly to protect the individual against police brutality and partly to make confessions credible to a jury, all interviews with a suspect are audio taped on a machine which make two simultaneous copies one for the police and one for the defendant. In Northern Ireland, where society is more polarised than in the rest of the United Kingdom, which means that allegations of police brutality are perceived by sections of the community to carry more credence, interviews are video taped.
Since the European Convention on Human Rights was adopted by the Council of Europe in 1950 to date there have been no prosecutions bought to the European Court of Human Rights where the ECHR have ruled that torture took place. It has been alleged that in certain circumstances torture, even though it is illegal, may have been used by some European countries. In "anti-terrorist" campaigns where information is needed for intelligence purposes, and not to obtain a confession for use in court, there is a temptation by the security forces, whether authorised by governments or not, to extract intelligence from alleged terrorists using any means available including the use of torture. Where there is a time component to a crime, for example in a kidnapping case, there is also a temptation for the police to try to extract information by methods which would nullify the use of such information in court.
[edit] Criticism
[edit] Proponents
Since the September 11, 2001 attacks the debate on torture in the United States has become more than just an academic exercise. Some scholars have argued that the need for information outweighs the moral and ethical arguments against torture.
Yasmin Alibhai-Brown in an opinion article[1] published in The Independent on 23 May 2005 wrote:
The Harvard law professor Alan Dershowitz argues that in extreme situations, in order to prevent a tragedy, a "torture warrant" should be issued by U.S. courts to use hot needles under the nails, for example. This would make the use open to security, even thought it would be against the Geneva conventions [and other international treaties]. This utilitarian position is both contemptible and persuasive...
Two academics at Deakin University in Victoria, Australia, Professor Mirko Bagaric, a Croatian born Australian based author and lawyer,[2] who is the head of Deakin University's Law School, and a fellow Deakin law lecturer, Julie Clarke, published a paper in the University of San Francisco Law Review arguing that when many lives are in imminent danger, "all forms of harm" may be inflicted on a suspect, even if this might result in "annihilation".The reasoning behind the proposal to legalise torture is that:[3]
as a society we would accept that one person being killed to save thousands is legitimate. ...
Of course, it is far more repugnant to inflict harm on an innocent person than a wrongdoer," said Professor Bagaric, "But in some extreme cases, where it is almost certain someone has information that could prevent many lives being lost and there is no other way to obtain that information, the mere fact that they're not directly involved in creating that threat doesn't mean they can wash their hands of responsibility.
It was observed that Bagaric "was not the author of what he wrote, all he did was reintroducing Alan M. Dershowitz’ thesis, Sharon’s [Israeli] government legal adviser and the theorist of the legal torture".[4]
On December 20, 2005, Albert Mohler, president of the Southern Baptist Theological Seminary addressed the problem of whether torture should be used by American military forces in order to gain important information from terrorist suspects. Although he spoke out against any form of legal codification, he did state the following:[5]
Under certain circumstances, most morally sensitive persons would surely allow interrogators to yell at prisoners and to use psychological intimidation, sleep deprivation, and the removal of creature comforts for purposes of obtaining vital information. In increasingly serious cases, most would likely allow some use of pharmaceuticals and more intensive and manipulative psychological techniques. In the most extreme of conceivable cases, most would also allow the use of far more serious mechanisms of coercion – even what we would all agree should be labeled as torture.
...I would argue that we cannot condone torture by codifying a list of exceptional situations in which techniques of torture might be legitimately used. At the same time, I would also argue that we cannot deny that there could exist circumstances in which such uses of torture might be made necessary.
[edit] Opponents
Although widely used through history, most experts agree that torture is an unreliable means of obtaining useful information. It does function as a means of controlling people through fear.
Amnesty International spokeswoman Nicole Bieske, who is also a lawyer, was stunned by the idea of regulating torture.
It's astonishing and appalling that somebody would hold this opinion in relation to such a fundamental issue as torture, and to be justifying it on moral as well as pragmatic grounds...[6]
Professor Bagaric and Mrs Clarke submitted the paper to an American law journal because:
they are more open to new ideas on human rights. ...
At my talk in the US, some people were for torture, some were against, but most people realised there were different sides of the argument...You didn't get the kind of emotive comments that I've had here in Australia, saying that this view is horrendous, unthinking, and irresponsible.[6]
On the other hand, objectively measurable facts and demonstrable results rarely exist in the real world of criminal justice and human psychology. It is difficult to determine what causes great pain except in the more extreme cases. To keep a suspect standing and awake for two hours is clearly not unreasonable. To do so for forty eight clearly is "inhuman or degrading treatment".[7] Somewhere in-between a line is crossed but it is impossible to say where. Nor is it clear that a view that does not care why something is done is ever morally justifiable.
[edit] Ticking time bomb scenario
It may be the case that not all ends justify all means, but to some commentators some ends justify some means. It has been suggested that in a few extreme cases it may even be true that not to use torture would be worse than using it.[citation needed] In law enforcement, one perceived argument is the necessity of force to extract information from a suspect when regular interrogation yields no results and time is of the essence, as can be seen in the most frequently cited theoretical example is the "ticking time bomb" scenario, where a known terrorist has planted a nuclear bomb. In such circumstances, it has been argued, that not to use torture would be wrong.
Supporters cite the case of Magnus Gäfgen, who was suspected of kidnapping 11-year-old Jakob von Metzler and arrested in October 2002 by German police. Police surveillance had observed Gäfgen pick up a €1 million ransom demanded from the von Metzler family and proceed to go on a spending spree. After the ransom was paid, the boy was not released. Fearing for the boy's safety Frankfurt's deputy police chief, Wolfgang Daschner, had Gäfgen arrested and when he would not talk threatened to cause Gäfgen severe pain. Gäfgen told police where he had hidden von Metzler's body. In this case torture was threatened, but not used, to extract information that, in other circumstances, could have saved a boy's life. The ethical question is whether this can ever be justified. Wolfgang Daschner felt that in the circumstances it was justified.
The obvious rebuttal to this stance is that no such scenario has ever existed. In addition, those situations resembling such a case were resolved without the need to torture any suspect. Furthermore, it is asked whether torture would be limited to suspects, or whether one could torture the family and friends of this detainee to make him compliant. Beyond that, another reason is that torture fails to elicit the expected information because the subject is saying anything interrogators want to hear to stop the ordeal, or worse: the detainee is innocent. By adopting a "the ends justifies the means" approach this would allow nine innocent people to be tortured as long as the tenth offered a full confession.
[edit] See also
[edit] References
- O'Brien, William V. "Law and Morality in Israel's War with the PLO". New York: Routledge. 1991.
[edit] Further reading
- AllHoff, Fritz;"A Defense of Torture: Separation of Cases, Ticking Time-bombs and Moral Justification"(pdf) International Journal of Applied Philosophy, Fall 2005
- Bagaric, Mirko; A case for torture May 17, 2005
- Bagaric, Mirko & Clarke Julie;Tortured Responses (A Reply to our Critics): Physically Persuading Suspects is Morally Preferable to Allowing the Innocent to be Murdered University of San Francisco Law Review, Volume 20, Spring 2006, Number 3
- Bagaric, Mirko & Clarke, Julie; Torture: When the Unthinkable is Morally Permissible, State University of New York Press, 2006.
- DW staff; Frankfurt Deputy Police Chief (Wolfgang Daschner) Charged in Torture Case, Deutsche Welle 20 February 2004
- Greek, Cecil E.; Introduction to Beccaria's Thought, Florida State University College of Criminology and Criminal Justice:
- Rumney, Phil; the current legal debate surrounding coercive interrogation: Could or should torture be legalised? Beating the Terrorists?(pdf), Sheffield Hallam University Law Matters: Issue Number 4 October 2006, Page 2
- http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/torture/
[edit] Footnotes
- ^ Yasmin Alibhai-Brown: People matter more than holy books Editorial and Opinion (Page 31) in The Independent Monday 23 May 2005. Includes commentary on how some Americans have changed their attitudes to torture.
- ^ Mirko Bagaric
- ^ Bagaric,Mirko & Clarke Julie;Not Enough Official Torture in the World? The Circumstances in Which Torture Is Morally Justifiable University of San Francisco Law Review, Volume 39, Spring 2005, Number 3, pp. 581-616.
- ^ Opinion-editorials decyphered: Torture: the visible part of the iceberg - 20 May 2005
- ^ Torture and the War on Terror: We Must Not Add Dirty Rules to Dirty Hands - albertmohler.com
- ^ a b Minchin,Liz. Make torture legal, say two academics, The Age 17 May, 2005
- ^ In 1978 the European Court of Human Rights ruled that the five techniques of "sensory deprivation" were not torture but were "inhuman or degrading treatment". See Accusations of use of torture by United Kingdom for details. This case was 9 years before the United Nations Convention Against Torture (UNCAT) came into force and had an influence on States thinking about what constitutes torture ever since.