Turing degree

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Post's problem redirects here. You may be seeking Post's correspondence problem

In computer science and mathematical logic, the Turing degree or degree of unsolvability of a set X of natural numbers is the equivalence class of all sets that are Turing equivalent to X. The concept of Turing degree is fundamental in computability theory.

The Turing degree of a set gives a measure of the level of algorithmic unsolvability of the set; two sets are equivalent if they have the same level of unsolvability. The Turing degrees are partially ordered so that if degree of a set X is less than degree of a set Y then the level of unsolvability of X is less than that of Y in the sense that any (noncomputable) procedure that correctly decides whether numbers are in Y can be effectively converted to a procedure that correctly decides whether numbers are in X.

The Turing degrees were introduced by Stephen Cole Kleene and Emil Leon Post in the 1940s and have been an area of intense research since then.

Contents

[edit] Turing equivalence

For the rest of this article, the word set will refer to a set of natural numbers. A set X is said to be Turing reducible to a set Y if there is an oracle Turing machine that decides membership in X when given an oracle for membership in Y. The notation XT Y indicates that X is Turing reducible to Y.

Two sets X and Y are defined to be Turing equivalent if X is Turing reducible to Y and Y is Turing reducible to X. The notation XT Y indicates that X and Y are Turing equivalent. The relation ≡T can be seen to be an equivalence relation, which means that for all sets X, Y, and Z:

  • XT X
  • XT Y implies YT X
  • If XT Y and YT Z then XT Z.

[edit] Turing degree

A Turing degree is an equivalence class of the relation ≡T. The notation [X] denotes the equivalence class containing a set X. The entire collection of Turing degrees is denoted \mathcal{D}.

The Turing degrees have an order relation ≤ defined so that [X] ≤ [Y] if and only if XT Y. This can be seen to be a partial order. There is a unique Turing degree containing all the computable sets, and this degree is less than every other degree. It is denoted 0 (zero) because it is the least element of the poset \mathcal{D}. (It is common to use boldface notation for Turing degrees, in order to distinguish them from sets. When no confusion can occur, such as with [X], the boldface is not necessary.)

For any sets X and Y the Turing join X ⊕ Y is defined to be the union of the sets {2n : nX } and {2m+1 : m ∈ Y}. It can be seen that the Turing degree of X ⊕ Y is the least upper bound of the degrees of X and Y. Thus \mathcal{D} is an upper semi-lattice. The least upper bound of degrees a and b is denoted ab. It is known that \mathcal{D} is not a lattice; there are pairs of degrees with no greatest lower bound.

For any set X the notation X′ denotes the set of indices of oracle machines that halt when using X as an oracle. The set X′ is called the Turing jump of X. The Turing jump of a degree [X] is defined to be the degree [X′]; this is a valid definition because X′ ≡T Y′ whenever XT Y. Thus, for example, the degree 0′ is the degree of the Halting problem.

[edit] Basic properties of the Turing degrees

  • Every Turing degree contains exactly \aleph_0 (that is, countably many) sets.
  • There are 2^{\aleph_0} Turing degrees.
  • For each degree a the strict inequality a < a′ holds.

[edit] Structure of the Turing degrees

A great deal of research has been conducted into the structure of the Turing degrees. The following survey lists only some of the many known results. One general conclusion that can be drawn from the research is that the structure of the Turing degrees is extremely complicated.

[edit] Order properties

  • There are minimal degrees. A degree a is minimal if a is nonzero and there is no degree between 0 and a.
  • For every nonzero degree a there is a degree b incomparable with a.
  • There is a set of 2^{\aleph_0} pairwise incomparable Turing degrees.
  • There are pairs of degrees with no greatest lower bound. Thus \mathcal{D} is not a lattice.
  • Every countable partially ordered set can be embedded in the Turing degrees.
  • No infinite increasing sequence of degrees has a least upper bound.

[edit] Properties involving the jump

  • For every degree a there is a degree strictly between a and a′. In fact, there is a countable sequence of pairwise incomparable degrees between a and a′.
  • A degree a is of the form b′ if and only if 0′a.
  • For any degree a there is a degree b such that a < b and b′ = a′; such a degree b is called low relative to a.
  • There is an infinite sequence ai of degrees such that ai+1ai for each i.

[edit] Logical properties

  • The first-order theory of \mathcal{D} in the language 〈 ≤, = 〉 or 〈 ≤, ′, =〉 is many-one equivalent to the theory of true second-order arithmetic. This indicates that the structure of \mathcal{D} is extremely complicated.
  • The jump operator is definable in the first-order structure of the degrees with the language 〈 ≤, =〉.

[edit] Structure of the r.e. Turing degrees

A degree is called r.e. (recursively enumerable) if it contains a recursively enumerable set. Every r.e. degree is less than or equal to 0′ but not every degree less than 0′ is an r.e. degree.

  • The r.e degrees are dense; between any two r.e. degrees there is a third r.e degree.
  • There are two r.e. degrees with no greatest lower bound in the r.e. degrees.
  • There is a pair of nonzero r.e. degrees whose greatest lower bound is 0.
  • Every finite distributive lattice can be embedded into the r.e. degrees. In fact, the countable atomless Boolean algebra can be embedded in a manner that preserves suprema and infima.
  • Not all finite lattices can be embedded in the r.e. degrees (via an embedding that preserves suprema and infima). The following particular lattice cannot be embedded in the r.e. degrees:
Image:rehasse.png
  • There is no pair of r.e. degrees whose greatest lower bound is 0 and whose least upper bound is 0′. This result is informally called the nondiamond theorem.
  • The first-order theory of the r.e. degrees in the language 〈 0, ≤, = 〉 is many-one equivalent to the theory of true first order arithmetic.

[edit] Post's problem and the priority method

Emil Post studied the r.e. Turing degrees and asked whether there is any r.e. degree strictly between 0 and 0′. The problem of constructing such a degree (or showing that none exist) became known as Post's problem. This problem was solved independently by Friedberg and Muchnik in the 1950s, who showed that these intermediate r.e. degrees do exist. Their proofs each developed the same new method for constructing r.e degrees which came to be known as the priority method. The priority method is now the main technique for establishing results about r.e. sets.

The idea of the priority method for constructing an r.e. set X is to list a countable sequence of requirements that X must satisfy. For example, to construct an r.e. set X between 0 and 0′ it is enough to satisfy the requirements Ae and Be for each natural number e, where Ae requires that the oracle machine with index e does not compute 0′ from X and Be requires that the Turing machine with index e (and no oracle) does not compute X. These requirements are put into a priority ordering, which is an explicit bijection of the requirements and the natural numbers. The proof proceeds inductively with one stage for each natural number; these stages can be thought of as steps of time during which the set X is enumerated. At each stage, numbers may put into X or forever prevented from entering X in an attempt to satisfy requirements (that is, force them to hold once all of X has been enumerated). Sometimes, a number can be enumerated into X to satisfy one requirement but doing this would cause a previously satisfied requirement to become unsatisfied (that is, to be injured). The priority order on requirements is used to determine which requirement to satisfy in this case. The informal idea is that if a requirement is injured then it will eventually stop being injured after all higher priority requirements have stopped being injured, although not every priority argument has this property. An argument must be made that the overall set X is r.e. and satisfies all the requirements. Priority arguments can be used to prove many facts about r.e. sets; the requirements used and the manner in which they are satisfied must be carefully chosen to produce the required result.

[edit] References

[edit] Monographs (undergraduate level)

Cooper, S.B. Computability theory. Chapman & Hall/CRC, Boca Raton, FL, 2004. ISBN 1-58488-237-9

Cutland, N. Computability. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge-New York, 1980. ISBN 0-521-22384-9; ISBN 0-521-29465-7

Odifreddi, P. Classical Recursion Theory, North-Holland, ISBN 0-444-87295-7

[edit] Monographs and survey articles (graduate level)

Ambos-Spies, K. and Fejer, P. Degrees of Unsolvability. Unpublished. http://www.cs.umb.edu/~fejer/articles/History_of_Degrees.pdf

Lerman, M. Degrees of unsolvability. Perspectives in Mathematical Logic. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1983. ISBN 3-540-12155-2

Rogers, H. The Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability, MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-68052-1; ISBN 0-07-053522-1

Simpson, S. Degrees of unsolvability: a survey of results. Handbook of Mathematical Logic, North-Holland, 1977, pp. 631--652.

Shore, R. The theories of the T, tt, and wtt r.e. degrees: undecidability and beyond. Proceedings of the IX Latin American Symposium on Mathematical Logic, Part 1 (Bahía Blanca, 1992), 61--70, Notas Lógica Mat., 38, Univ. Nac. del Sur, Bahía Blanca, 1993.

Soare, R. Recursively enumerable sets and degrees. Perspectives in Mathematical Logic. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1987. ISBN 3-540-15299-7

Soare, Robert I. Recursively enumerable sets and degrees. Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 84 (1978), no. 6, 1149--1181.