Independence of irrelevant alternatives
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Independence of irrelevant alternatives (IIA) is a term for an axiom of decision theory and various social sciences. Although exact formulations of IIA differ, intentions of the usages are similar in attempting to provide a rational account of individual behavior or aggregation of individual preferences.
Under one common formulation, the axiom states that:
- If A is preferred to B out of the choice set {A,B}, then introducing a third alternative X, thus expanding the choice set to {A,B,X}, must not make B preferred to A.
In other words, whether A or B is better should not be changed by the availability of X, which is irrelevant to the choice between A and B. This formulation appears in bargaining theory, theories of individual choice, and voting theory. It is controversial for two reasons: first, some theorists find it too strict an axiom; second, experiments by Amos Tversky, Daniel Kahneman, and others have showed that human behaviour rarely adheres to this axiom.
A distinct formulation of IIA is that of social choice theory:
- If A is selected over B out of the choice set {A,B} by a voting rule for given voter preferences of A, B, and an unavailable third alternative X, then B must not selected over A by the voting rule if only preferences for X change.
In other words, whether A or B is selected should not be affected by a change in the vote for an unavailable X, which is thus irrelevant to the choice between A and B. Kenneth Arrow (1951) shows the impossibility of aggregating individual preferences ("votes") satisfying IIA and certain other apparently reasonable conditions.
Contents |
[edit] Voting theory
In voting systems, independence of irrelevant alternatives is often interpreted as, if one candidate (X) wins the election, and a new alternative (Y) is added, only X or Y will win the election.
Approval voting and range voting satisfy the independence of irrelevant alternatives criterion, largely because they are cardinal rather than ordinal voting systems and votes for one candidate do not restrict votes for another. Another cardinal system, cumulative voting, does not satisfy the criterion.
An anecdote which illustrates a violation of this property has been attributed to Sidney Morgenbesser:
- After finishing dinner, Sidney Morgenbesser decides to order dessert. The waitress tells him he has two choices: apple pie and blueberry pie. Sidney orders the apple pie. After a few minutes the waitress returns and says that they also have cherry pie at which point Morgenbesser says "In that case I'll have the blueberry pie."
All voting systems have some degree of inherent susceptibility to strategic nomination considerations. Some regard these considerations as less serious unless the voting system specifically fails the (easier to satisfy) independence of clones criterion.
[edit] Local independence
A related criterion proposed by H. P. Young and A. Levenglick is called local independence of irrelevant alternatives. It says that if one candidate (X) wins an election, and a new alternative (Y) is added, X will still win the election if Y is not in the Smith set. In other words, the outcome of the election is independent of alternatives which are not in the Smith set. Note that this neither implies nor is implied by the independence of irrelevant alternatives criterion; in fact, the two are mutually exclusive.
No deterministic ranked methods satisfy IIA, but local IIA is satisfied by some methods which always elect from the Smith set, such as ranked pairs and Schulze method.
[edit] Criticism
Many voting theorists believe that IIA is too strong a condition. The majority criterion is incompatible with IIA. Consider
- 7 votes for A > B > C
- 6 votes for B > C > A
- 5 votes for C > A > B
Without loss of generality, suppose a voting system satisfying the majority criterion chooses A. If B drops out of the race, the remaining votes will be:
- 7 votes for A > C
- 11 votes for C > A
and C will win under the majority criterion, even though the change (B dropping out) concerned an "irrelevant" alternative candidate who did not win in the original circumstance. This is an example of the spoiler effect.
Some text of this article is derived with permission from http://condorcet.org/emr/criteria.shtml
[edit] IIA in social choice theory
From Kenneth Arrow (1951, pp. 15, 23, 27), each "voter" i in the society has an ordering Ri that ranks the (conceivable) objects of social choice -- X, Y, and Z in simplest case -- from lowest on up (say candidates for public office or social states from different economic policies). The voting rule in turn maps the set of voter orderings (R1, ...,Rn) onto a social ordering R that determines the social ranking of X, Y, and Z. Among the objects of choice, Arrow distinguishes those that by hypothesis are specified as feasible and infeasible. Consider two possible sets of voter orderings (R1, ...,Rn ) and (R1', ...,Rn') such that the ranking of X and Y for each voter i is the same for Ri and Ri'. The voting rule generates corresponding social orderings R and R'. Now suppose that X and Y are feasible but Z is infeasible (say, the candidate is not on the ballot or the social state is outside the production possibility curve). Arrow's IIA requires of the voting rule that R and R' select the same (top-ranked) social choice from the feasible set (X, Y). This requirement holds no matter what the ranking is of infeasible Z relative to X and Y in the two sets of orderings. Paramesh Ray (1973) shows that Arrow's IIA does not imply an IIA similar to that at the top of this article nor conversely.
[edit] IIA in econometrics
The independence of irrelevant alternatives (IIA) in econometrics is an assumption of the multinomial logit model in econometrics; outcomes that could theoretically violate this IIA (such as the outcome of multicandidate elections or any choice made by humans) may make multinomial logit an invalid estimator.
IIA implies that adding another alternative or changing the characteristics of a third alternative does not affect the relative odds between the two alternatives considered. This implication is not realistic for applications with similar alternatives. A well-known example is due to McFadden (1974). Consider commuters initially choosing between two modes of transportation: car and red bus. Suppose that a consumer chooses between busses with equal probability, 0.5, so that the odds equal 1. Now suppose a third mode, blue bus, is added. Assuming bus commuters do not care about the color of the bus, consumers are expected to choose between bus and car still with equal probability. But IIA implies that this is not the case: the probability of commuters that take each of the three modes equals one third. (based on Wooldridge 2002, pp.501-2)
Conditional probit (also called multinomial probit), conditional logit and mixed logit are alternative models for nominal outcomes that do not violate IIA, but often have assumptions of their own that may be difficult to meet or are computationally infeasible. The conditional logit model may be used if the structure of decision-making can be reduced to a series of binary choices; this approach also avoids the IIA assumption. The conditional probit model has as a disadvantage that it makes calculation of maximum likelihood infeasible for more than five alternatives as it involves multiple integrals. IIA can also be relaxed by specifying a hierarchical model, ranking the choice alternatives. The most popular of these is called the nested logit model (McFadden 1984).
[edit] References
- This entry is related to, but not included in the elections and voting series. Other related articles can be found at the Politics Portal.
- Kenneth J. Arrow, 1951, Social Choice and Individual Values
- Paramesh Ray, Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives, Econometrica, Vol. 41, No. 5 (September 1973), pp. 987-991. Discusses and deduces the (not always recognized) differences between various formulations of IIA.
- Peter Kennedy, 2003, 5th ed., A Guide to Econometrics
[edit] External links
- Steven Callander and Catherine H.Wilson, "Context-dependent Voting," Quarterly Journal of Political Science, 2006, 1: 227–254