History of calculus
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
- See also: History of mathematics
The origins of integral calculus are generally regarded as going no farther back than to the ancient India, though there is evidence that the ancient Egyptians may have harbored such knowledge as well (see Moscow Mathematical Papyrus).
Contents |
[edit] Development of Calculus
[edit] Indian Mathematicians
In 499, the mathematician-astronomer Aryabhata first used infinitesimals and expressed an astronomical problem in the form of a basic differential equation.[1] This equation eventually led Bhaskara in the 12th century to develop a theorem now known as "Rolle's theorem," which is a special case of the mean value theorem. He was also the first to define the notion of the derivative as a limit. In the 14th century, Madhava, along with other mathematician-astronomers of the Kerala School, studied infinite series, power series, Taylor series, convergence, differentiation, integration, the mean value theorem, and other ideas essential in proving the fundamental theorem of calculus.[2] Yuktibhasa, which some consider to be the first text on calculus, summarizes these results.[3][4][5]
A few have suggested that the contributions of the Kerala School to calculus were transmitted to Europe, but this is not known for certain.[6] (See Possible transmission of Kerala mathematics to Europe.)
[edit] Ancient Greece
Greek Geometers are credited with a significant use of infinitesimals. Democritus is first recorded to seriously consider the division of objects into an infinite number of cross-sections, but his inability to rationalize discrete cross-sections with a cone's smooth slope prevented him from accepting the idea. During approximately the same time, Zeno of Elea discredited infinitesimals further by his articulation of paradoxes which they create.
Antiphon and later Eudoxus are generally credited with implimenting the method of exhaustion, which made it possible to compute the area and volume of regions and solids by breaking them up into an infinite number of recognizable shapes. Archimedes developed this method further, while also inventing heuristic methods which resemble modern day concepts somewhat. (See Archimedes on Spheres & Cylinders.) It was not until the time of Newton that these methods were made obsolete.
It should not be thought that infinitesimals were put on rigorous footing during this time, however. Only when it is supplemented by a proper geometric proof would Greek Mathematicians accept a proposition as true.
See also: Archimedes' use of infinitesimals
[edit] Later Integrations
In the 15th century, a German cardinal named Nicholas of Cusa successfully argued that rules made for finite quantities lose their validity when applied to infinite ones, thus putting to rest Zeno's paradoxes.
In 17th century Europe, Isaac Barrow, Pierre de Fermat, Blaise Pascal, John Wallis and others discussed the idea of a derivative. René Descartes introduced the foundation for the methods of analytic geometry in 1637, providing the foundation for calculus later introduced by Isaac Newton and Gottfried Leibniz, independently of each other. Fermat, among other things, is credited with an ingenious trick for evaluating the integral of any power function directly, thus providing a valuable clue to Newton and Leibniz in their development of the fundamental theorems of calculus. James Gregory was able to prove a restricted version of the second fundamental theorem of calculus.
In this time, there was also a great deal of work being done by Japanese mathematicians, particularly Kowa Seki. [1] He made a number of contributions, namely in methods of determining areas of figures using integrals, extending the work of Archimedes. While these methods of finding areas were made largely obsolete by the development of the fundamental theorems by Newton and Leibniz, they still show that a sophisticated knowledge of mathematics existed in 17th century Japan.
Newton and Leibniz are usually credited with the invention of modern calculus in the late 1600s. Their most important contributions were the development of the fundamental theorem of calculus. Also, Leibniz did a great deal of work with developing consistent and useful notation and concepts. Newton was the first to organize the field into one consistent subject, and also provided some of the first and most important applications, especially of integral calculus. Of course, important contributions were also made by Barrow, Descartes, de Fermat, Huygens, Wallis and many others.
[edit] Newton and Leibniz
Historically, there was much debate over whether it was Newton or Leibniz who first "invented" calculus. This argument, the Newton v. Leibniz calculus controversy between the German Leibniz and the English Newton, was at the heart of a rift in the mathematical community of the two countries. Much of the credit for the resolution goes to the Analytical Society.
Much of the controversy centers on certain early manuscripts of Newton's that Leibniz may have had access to. Newton began his work on calculus at least as early as 1666, giving plenty of time for this to occur, as Leibniz did not begin his work until 1676. Leibniz was in England in 1673 and 1676, and probably did see some of Newton's manuscripts. It is not known how much this may have influenced Leibniz. Both Newton and Leibniz claimed that the other plagiarized their respective works.
This controversy between Leibniz and Newton divided English-speaking mathematicians from those in Europe for many years, which slowed the development of mathematical analysis. Today, both Newton and Leibniz are given credit for independently developing calculus. It is Leibniz, however, who is credited with giving the new discipline the name it is known by today: "calculus". Newton's name for it was "the science of fluxions".
The work of both Newton and Leibniz is reflected in the notation used today. Newton was responsible for the and the notations, both very common in physics and mathematics. Leibniz was responsible for the notation that is also very popular, particularly for problems in multivariate calculus.
[edit] Rigorous foundations
Calculus was widely used, as it was a very powerful mathematical tool, but it was not until the mid-1800s that it was put on a rigorous foundation from the modern viewpoint. For example, while the definition of the derivative itself has not changed since it was first introduced, it requires the notion of a limit. Newton, Leibniz, and their immediate successors interpreted limits intuitively instead of through precise definitions. This was standard practice at the time. Later, with the work of mathematicians like Augustin Louis Cauchy, Bernard Bolzano, and Karl Weierstrass, the foundations of calculus were clarified and made precise. The study of foundations eventually resulted in deep explorations of the concept of infinity by Georg Cantor and others.
[edit] Integrals
Niels Henrik Abel seems to have been the first to consider in a general way the question as to what differential expressions can be integrated in a finite form by the aid of ordinary functions, an investigation extended by Liouville. Cauchy early undertook the general theory of determining definite integrals, and the subject has been prominent during the 19th century. Frullani's theorem (1821), Bierens de Haan's work on the theory (1862) and his elaborate tables (1867), Dirichlet's lectures (1858) embodied in Meyer's treatise (1871), and numerous memoirs of Legendre, Poisson, Plana, Raabe, Sohncke, Schlömilch, Elliott, Leudesdorf, and Kronecker are among the noteworthy contributions.
Eulerian integrals were first studied by Euler and afterwards investigated by Legendre, by whom they were classed as Eulerian integrals of the first and second species, as follows:
although these were not the exact forms of Euler's study. If n is an integer, it follows that , but the integral converges for all positive real n and defines an analytic continuation of the factorial function to all of the complex plane except for poles at zero and the negative integers. To it Legendre assigned the symbol Γ, and it is now called the gamma function. Besides being analytic over the positive reals, Γ also enjoys the uniquely defining property that logΓ is convex, which aesthetically justifies this analytic continuation of the factorial function over any other analytic continuation. To the subject Dirichlet has contributed an important theorem Liouville, 1839), which has been elaborated by Liouville, Catalan, Leslie Ellis, and others. On the evaluation of Γ(x) and logΓ(x) Raabe (1843-44), Bauer (1859), and Gudermann (1845) have written. Legendre's great table appeared in 1816.
[edit] Symbolic methods
Symbolic methods may be traced back to Taylor, and the analogy between successive differentiation and ordinary exponentials had been observed by numerous writers before the nineteenth century. Arbogast (1800) was the first, however, to separate the symbol of operation from that of quantity in a differential equation. François (1812) and Servois (1814) seem to have been the first to give correct rules on the subject. Hargreave (1848) applied these methods in his memoir on differential equations, and Boole freely employed them. Grassmann and Hermann Hankel made great use of the theory, the former in studying equations, the latter in his theory of complex numbers.
[edit] Calculus of variations
The calculus of variations may be said to begin with a problem of Johann Bernoulli's (1696). It immediately occupied the attention of Jakob Bernoulli and the Marquis de l'Hôpital, but Euler first elaborated the subject. His contributions began in 1733, and his Elementa Calculi Variationum gave to the science its name. Lagrange contributed extensively to the theory, and Legendre (1786) laid down a method, not entirely satisfactory, for the discrimination of maxima and minima. To this discrimination Brunacci (1810), Gauss (1829), Poisson (1831), Ostrogradsky (1834), and Jacobi (1837) have been among the contributors. An important general work is that of Sarrus (1842) which was condensed and improved by Cauchy (1844). Other valuable treatises and memoirs have been written by Strauch (1849), Jellett (1850), Hesse (1857), Clebsch (1858), and Carll (1885), but perhaps the most important work of the century is that of Weierstrass. His celebrated course on the theory is epoch-making, and it may be asserted that he was the first to place it on a firm and unquestionable foundation.
[edit] Applications
The application of the infinitesimal calculus to problems in physics and astronomy was contemporary with the origin of the science. All through the eighteenth century these applications were multiplied, until at its close Laplace and Lagrange had brought the whole range of the study of forces into the realm of analysis. To Lagrange (1773) we owe the introduction of the theory of the potential into dynamics, although the name "potential function" and the fundamental memoir of the subject are due to Green (1827, printed in 1828). The name "potential" is due to Gauss (1840), and the distinction between potential and potential function to Clausius. With its development are connected the names of Dirichlet, Riemann, Neumann, Heine, Kronecker, Lipschitz, Christoffel, Kirchhoff, Beltrami, and many of the leading physicists of the century.
It is impossible in this place to enter into the great variety of other applications of analysis to physical problems. Among them are the investigations of Euler on vibrating chords; Sophie Germain on elastic membranes; Poisson, Lamé, Saint-Venant, and Clebsch on the elasticity of three-dimensional bodies; Fourier on heat diffusion; Fresnel on light; Maxwell, Helmholtz, and Hertz on electricity; Hansen, Hill, and Gyldén on astronomy; Maxwell on spherical harmonics; Lord Rayleigh on acoustics; and the contributions of Dirichlet, Weber, Kirchhoff, F. Neumann, Lord Kelvin, Clausius, Bjerknes, MacCullagh, and Fuhrmann to physics in general. The labors of Helmholtz should be especially mentioned, since he contributed to the theories of dynamics, electricity, etc., and brought his great analytical powers to bear on the fundamental axioms of mechanics as well as on those of pure mathematics.
Furthermore, infinitesimal calculus was introduced into the social sciences, starting with Neoclassical economics. Today, it is a valuable tool in mainstream economics.
[edit] Notes
- ^ Aryabhata the Elder
- ^ Madhava. Biography of Madhava. School of Mathematics and Statistics University of St Andrews, Scotland. Retrieved on 2006-09-13.
- ^ An overview of Indian mathematics. Indian Maths. School of Mathematics and Statistics University of St Andrews, Scotland. Retrieved on 2006-07-07.
- ^ Science and technology in free India. Government of Kerala — Kerala Call, September 2004. Prof.C.G.Ramachandran Nair. Retrieved on 2006-07-09.
- ^ Charles Whish (1835). Transactions of the Royal Asiatic Society of Great Britain and Ireland.
- ^ Neither Newton nor Leibniz - The Pre-History of Calculus and Celestial Mechanics in Medieval Kerala. MAT 314. Canisius College. Retrieved on 2006-07-09.