Cut-elimination theorem

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

The cut-elimination theorem is the central result establishing the significance of the sequent calculus. It was originally proved by Gerhard Gentzen in his landmark paper "Investigations in Logical Deduction" for the systems LJ and LK formalising intuitionistic and classical logic respectively. The cut-elimination theorem (Hauptsatz) states that any judgement that possesses a proof in the sequent calculus that makes use of the cut rule also possesses a cut-free proof, that is, a proof that does not make use of the cut rule.

A sequent is a logical expression relating multiple sentences, in the form "A, B, C, \ldots \vdash N, O, P", which is to be read as "A, B, C, \ldots proves N, O, P", and (as glossed by Gentzen) should be understood as equivalent to the truth-function "If (A and B and C \ldots) then (N or O or P)." Note that the left-hand side (LHS) is a conjunction (and) and the RHS is a disjunction (or). The LHS may have arbitrarily many or few formulae; when the LHS is empty, the RHS is a tautology. In LK, the RHS may also have any number of formulae—if it has none, the LHS is a contradiction, whereas in LJ the RHS may have only none or one formula: here we see that allowing more than one formula in the RHS is equivalent, in the presence of the right contraction rule, to the admissibility of the law of the excluded middle. However, the sequent calculus is a fairly expressive framework, and there have been sequent calculi for intuitionistic logic proposed that allow many formulae in the RHS. From Jean-Yves Girard's logic LC it is easy to obtain a rather natural formalisation of classical logic where the RHS contains at most one formula; it is the interplay of the logical and structural rules that is the key here.

"Cut" is a rule in the normal statement of the sequent calculus, and equivalent to a variety of rules in other proof theories, which, given

(1) (A, B, \ldots) \vdash C

and

(2) C \vdash (D, E, \ldots)

allows one to infer

(3) (A, B, \ldots) \vdash (D, E, \ldots)

That is, it "cuts" the occurrences of the formula "C" out of the inferential relation.

The cut-elimination theorem states that (for a given system) any sequent provable using the rule Cut can be proved without use of this rule. If we think of (D, E, \ldots) as a theorem, then cut-elimination simply says that a lemma C used to prove this theorem can be inlined. Whenever the theorem's proof mentions lemma C, we can substitute the occurrences for the proof of C. Consequently, the cut rule is admissible.

For systems formulated in the sequent calculus, analytic proofs are those proofs that do not use Cut. Typically such a proof will be longer, of course, and not necessarily trivially so. In his essay "Don't Eliminate Cut!" George Boolos demonstrated that there was a derivation that could be completed in a page using cut, but whose analytic proof could not be completed in the lifespan of the universe.

The theorem has many, rich consequences. Once a system is shown to have a cut elimination theorem, it is normally immediate that the system is consistent. Normally also the system has the subformula property, an important property in several approaches to proof-theoretic semantics. Cut elimination is one of the most powerful tools for proving interpolation theorems. The possibility of carrying out proof search based on resolution, the essential insight leading to the Prolog programming language, depends upon the admissibility of Cut in the appropriate system.

[edit] External links

In other languages