Correlation does not imply causation

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Correlation does not imply causation is a phrase used in statistics to indicate that correlation between two variables does not imply there is a cause-and-effect relationship between the two. Its negation correlation implies causation is a logical fallacy by which two events that occur together are prematurely claimed to have a cause-and-effect relationship. It is also known as cum hoc ergo propter hoc (Latin for "with this, therefore because of this") and false cause.

Contents

[edit] Usage

The widely used phrase "Correlation does not imply causation" from one definition of the term imply may sometimes be incorrect. In logic, imply means:

  • To involve as a necessary circumstance. - which makes the above phrase correct.

This is the meaning intended by stasticians when they use the phrase. Indeed, p implies q has the technical meaning of logical implication: if p then q symbolized as p ⇒ q.

In everyday English, "imply" may in some cases mean:

  • To indicate or suggest.

However, the phrase "Correlation does not suggest causation" is not necessarily true: Demonstrably consistent correlation often suggests or increases the probability of some causal relationship (or implies it, in the latter sense of the term). What it does not do is prove causation, as arguments which use the fallacy as a pattern of reasoning assert. [1]

[edit] General pattern

Cum hoc ergo propter hoc is a less specific post hoc ergo propter hoc, without time as correlation factor. It can be expressed as follows:

  • A occurs in correlation to B.
  • Therefore, A causes B.

In this type of logical fallacy, one makes a premature conclusion about causality after observing only a correlation between two or more factors. Generally, if one factor (A) is observed to only be correlated with another factor (B), it is sometimes taken for granted that A is causing B even when no evidence supports this. This is a logical fallacy because there are at least four other possibilities:

  1. B may be the cause of A, or
  2. some unknown third factor is actually the cause of the relationship between A and B, or
  3. the "relationship" is so complex it can be labelled coincidental (i.e., two events occurring at the same time that have no simple relationship to each other besides the fact that they are occurring at the same time).
  4. B may be the cause of A at the same time as A is the cause of B (contradicting that the only relationship between A and B is that A causes B). This describes a self-reinforcing system.

In other words, there can be no conclusion made regarding the existence or the direction of a cause and effect relationship only from the fact that A is correlated with B. Determining whether there is an actual cause and effect relationship requires further investigation, even when the relationship between A and B is statistically "strong".

[edit] Examples

Sleeping with one's shoes on is strongly correlated with waking up with a headache.
Therefore, sleeping with one's shoes on causes headache.

The above example commits the correlation implies causation fallacy, as it prematurely concludes that sleeping with one's shoes on causes headache. A more plausible explanation is that both are caused by a third factor, in this case alcohol intoxication, which thereby gives rise to a correlation. Thus, this is a case of possibility (2) above.

A recent scientific example:

Young children who sleep with the light on are much more likely to develop myopia in later life.

This result of a study at University of Pennsylvania Medical Center was published in the May 13, 1999, issue of Nature and received much coverage at the time in the popular press [2]. However a later study at Ohio State University did not find any link between infants sleeping with the light on and developing myopia but did find a strong link between parental myopia and the development of child myopia and also noted that myopic parents were more likely to leave a light on in their children's bedroom [3]. This is a case of (2).

Another example:

Since the 1950s, both the atmospheric CO2 level and crime levels have increased sharply.
Hence, atmospheric CO2 causes crime.

The above example arguably makes the mistake of prematurely concluding a causal relationship where the relationship between the variables, if any, is so complex it may be labelled coincidental. The two events have no simple relationship to each other beside the fact that they are occurring at the same time. This is a case of possibility (3) above.

Another example:

Not eating causes anorexia nervosa.

Depending on the evidence used to support this statement, it can be shown that this is a correlation implies causation error of either type (1) or (4) described above. Having the disease Anorexia Nervosa may be the cause of not eating. This could, however, also be an example of case (4): It is correct that not eating does cause anorexia nervosa, but it can also be claimed that having developed anorexia nervosa causes one not to eat. Empirical evidence would be necessary to make a causative statement.

A more complex example:

Scientific research finds that people who use cannabis (A) have a higher prevalence of psychiatric disorders compared to those who do not (B).

This particular correlation is sometimes used to support the theory that the use of cannabis causes a psychiatric disorder (A is the cause of B). Although this may be possible, we cannot automatically discern a cause and effect relationship from research that has only determined people who use cannabis are more likely to develop a psychiatric disorder. From the same research, it can also be the case that (1.) having the predisposition for a psychiatric disorder causes these individuals to use cannabis (B causes A), OR (2.) it may be the case that in the above study some unknown third factor (e.g., poverty) is the actual cause for there being found a higher number of people (compared to the general public) who both use cannabis and who have been diagnosed as having a psychiatric disorder. Alternatively, it may be that the effects of cannabis are found more pleasureable by persons with certain psychiatric disorders. To assume that A causes B is tempting, but further scientific investigation of the type that can isolate extraneous variables is needed when research has only determined a statistical correlation.

The Flying Spaghetti Monsterism, a parody religion founded in 2005, satirically believes that there is a correlation between the number of pirates and many natural disasters. Bobby Henderson, the creator of this religion, put forth the argument that:

Global warming, earthquakes, hurricanes, and other natural disasters are a direct effect of the shrinking numbers of pirates since the 1800s.[4]

This helps to show that things with statistically significant correlations are not necessarily related.

An episode of The Simpsons (Season 7, "Much Apu About Nothing") serves as a good example of this principle. Springfield had just spent millions of dollars creating a highly sophisticated "Bear Patrol" in response to the sighting of a single bear the week before.

Homer: Not a bear in sight. The "Bear Patrol" is working like a charm!
Lisa: That's specious reasoning, Dad.
Homer: [uncomprehendingly] Thanks, honey.
Lisa: By your logic, I could claim that this rock keeps tigers away.
Homer: Hmm. How does it work?
Lisa: It doesn't work. (pause) It's just a stupid rock!
Homer: Uh-huh.
Lisa: But I don't see any tigers around, do you?
Homer: (pause) Lisa, I want to buy your rock.

[edit] Determining causation

David Hume argued[citation needed] that causality cannot be perceived (and therefore cannot be known or proven), and instead we can only perceive correlation. However, he argued[citation needed] that we can use the scientific method to rule out false causes.

In modern science, causation is defined by a counterfactual.[citation needed] Suppose that a student performed poorly on a test and guesses that the cause was not studying. To prove this, we think of the counterfactual - the same student writing the same test under the same circumstances, but having studied the night before. This counterfactual is certainly possible, but it is not what happened and so the counterfactual test score cannot be observed. If we could rewind history, and change only one small thing (making the student study for the exam), then causation could be observed (by comparing version 1 to version 2). Because we cannot rewind history and replay events after making small controlled changes, causation can only be inferred, never exactly known. This is referred to as the Fundamental Problem of Causal Inference[citation needed] - it is impossible to directly observe causal effects.[citation needed]

The central goal of scientific experiments and statistical methods is to approximate as best as possible the counterfactual state of the world.[citation needed] For example, one could run an experiment on identical twins who were known to consistently get the same grades on their tests. One twin is sent to study for six hours while the other is sent to the amusement park. If their test scores suddenly diverged by a large degree, this would be strong evidence that studying (or going to the amusement park) had a causal effect on test scores. In this case, correlation between studying and test scores would almost certainly imply causation.[citation needed]

Well designed statistical studies replace equality of individuals as in the previous example by equality of groups.[citation needed] This is achieved by randomization of the subjects to two or more groups. Placing the subjects randomly in the treatment/placebo groups, ensure that it is highly likely that the groups are reasonably equal in all relevant aspects.[citation needed] If the treatment has a significant different effect than the placebo, one can conclude that the treatment is likely to have a causal effect on the disease. This likeliness can be quantified in statistical terms by the P-value.[citation needed]

[edit] See also

[edit] References and notes

  1. ^ Karl L. Wuensch, Department of Psychology, East Carolina University When does correlation imply causation?
  2. ^ CNN, May 13, 1999. Night-light may lead to nearsightedness.
  3. ^ Ohio State University Research News, March 9, 2000. Night lights don't lead to nearsightedness, study suggests.
  4. ^ Henderson, Bobby (2005). Church of the Flying Spaghetti Monster (HTML). Retrieved on 2006-06-11.

[edit] External links