Cardinality of the continuum

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

In mathematics, the cardinality of the continuum is the cardinal number of the set of real numbers R (sometimes called the continuum). This cardinal number is often denoted by c,

\mathfrak c = |\mathbb R|

Contents

[edit] Properties

[edit] Uncountability

Georg Cantor introduced the concept of cardinality to compare the sizes of infinite sets. He famously showed that the set of real numbers is uncountably infinite; i.e. c is strictly greater than the cardinality of the natural numbers, \aleph_0 (aleph-null):

\aleph_0 < \mathfrak c

In other words, there are strictly more real numbers than there are integers. Cantor proved this statement in several different ways. See Cantor's first uncountability proof and Cantor's diagonal argument.

[edit] Cardinal equalities

A variation on Cantor's diagonal argument can be used to prove Cantor's theorem which states that the cardinality of any set is strictly less than that of its power set, i.e. |A| < 2|A|. One concludes that the power set P(N) of the natural numbers N is uncountable. It is then natural to ask whether the cardinality of P(N) is equal to c. It turns out that the answer is yes. One can prove this in two steps:

  1. Define a map f : RP(Q) from the reals to the power set of the rationals by sending each real number x to the set \{q \in \mathbb{Q} | q \le x\} of all rationals less than or equal to x (with the reals viewed as Dedekind cuts, this is nothing other than the inclusion map in the set of sets of rationals). This map is injective since the rationals are dense in R. Since the rationals are countable we have that \mathfrak c \le 2^{\aleph_0}.
  2. Let {0,2}N be the set of infinite sequences with values in set {0,2}. This set clearly has cardinality 2^{\aleph_0} (the natural bijection between the set of binary sequences and P(N) is given by the indicator function). Now associate to each such sequence (ai) the unique real number in the interval [0,1] with the ternary-expansion given by the digits (ai), i.e. the i-th digit after the decimal point is ai. The image of this map is called the Cantor set. It is not hard to see that this map is injective, for by avoiding points with the digit 1 in their ternary expansion we avoid conflicts created by the fact that the ternary-expansion of a real number is not unique. We then have that 2^{\aleph_0} \le \mathfrak c.

By the Cantor–Bernstein–Schroeder theorem we conclude that

\mathfrak c = |\mathcal{P}(\mathbb{N})| = 2^{\aleph_0}.

The sequence of beth numbers is defined by setting \beth_0 = \aleph_0 and \beth_{k+1} = 2^{\beth_k}. So c is the first beth number, beth-one

\mathfrak c = \beth_1

The second beth number, \beth_2 = 2^\mathfrak c, is the cardinality of the set of all subsets of the real line.

By using the rules of cardinal arithmetic one can show that

\mathfrak c = n \mathfrak c = \aleph_0 \mathfrak c = \mathfrak c^n = n^{\aleph_0} = {\aleph_0}^{\aleph_0} = \mathfrak c^{\aleph_0}

where n is any finite cardinal ≥ 2.

[edit] The continuum hypothesis

The famous continuum hypothesis asserts that c is also the first aleph number \aleph_1. In other words, the continuum hypothesis states that there is no set A whose cardinality lies strictly between \aleph_0 and c

\not\exists A : \aleph_0 < |A| < \mathfrak c

However, this statement is now known to be independent of the axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory (ZFC). That is, both the hypothesis and its negation are consistent with these axioms. In fact, for every nonzero natural number n, the equality c = \aleph_n is independent of ZFC. (The case n = 1 is the continuum hypothesis.) The same is true for most other alephs, although in some cases equality can be ruled out by König's theorem on the grounds of cofinality, e.g., \mathfrak{c}\neq\aleph_\omega. In particular, \mathfrak{c} could be either \aleph_1 or \aleph_{\omega_1}, where ω1 is the first uncountable ordinal, so it could be either a successor cardinal or a limit cardinal, and either a regular cardinal or a singular cardinal.

[edit] Sets with cardinality c

A great many sets studied in mathematics have cardinality equal to c. Some common examples are the following:


This article incorporates material from cardinality of the continuum on PlanetMath, which is licensed under the GFDL.

In other languages